Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science: A History (Third Edition). Thomas J. Hickey
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science: A History (Third Edition) - Thomas J. Hickey страница
Twentieth-Century
Philosophy of Science
A History
Thomas J. Hickey
Third Edition
© Registered Copyright 1995, 2005, 2016 by Thomas J. Hickey
ISBN-10: 0-692-65073-3
ISBN-13: 978-0-692-65073-8
Q174.8 .H 2016
Dewey 190.9004
Converted by www.ebookit.com
Published in e-book format by Thomas J. Hickey.
No part of this book may be reproduced for profit in any form or in any electronic or other medium including information storage and retrieval systems without written permission from the author.
Not-for-profit use with citation referencing Thomas J. Hickey is hereby permitted.
Other books by the Author:
Introduction to Metascience: An Information Science Approach to Methodology of Scientific Research.
Philosophy of Science: An Introduction.
A PROVOCATIVE PREFACE
In his magisterial two-volume Types of Economic Theory Wesley Clair Mitchell, Columbia University American Institutionalist economist, business-cycle economic historian, historian of economic theory and founder of the National Bureau of Economic Research, wrote that the process that constitutes the development of the social sciences is an incessant interaction between logically arranged ideas and chronologically arranged events.
Since modern science is an evolving cultural institution, this memorable Institutionalist refrain can be modified to apply to philosophy of science: The process that constitutes the development of philosophy of science is an episodic interaction between logically arranged ideas in philosophy and chronologically arranged events science. For the contemporary pragmatist philosopher of science the most important episodes in twentieth-century science are the two great scientific revolutions in physics – Einstein’s relativity physics and Heisenberg’s quantum physics – with the latter’s the more influential for philosophy.
This third edition of my Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science: A History is a revised and enlarged edition of my 1995 print book titled History of Twentieth-Century Philosophy of Science, which is now out of print. The greatly expanded “Introduction” chapter set forth herein as “BOOK I” summarizes the fundamental principles of the contemporary pragmatist philosophy of science, and includes discussion of the recently emergent specialty called “computational philosophy of science”. Each of the remaining chapters, BOOK II through BOOK VIII, focuses on selected authors who have influenced twentieth-century philosophy of science.
BOOK VIII on mechanized discovery systems is distinctive, because its subject still has little representation in the literature of academic philosophy. Computational philosophy of science is demanding, because it requires a working competence both in computer systems and in basic research in an empirical science. However, few academic philosophers have acquired such competencies, even though the system designs are manifestly relevant to philosophy of science. To date functioning discovery systems that have been used in science (including my METAMODEL system) have been developed by scientists working in their specialized sciences.
Nonetheless in the twentieth century’s latter decades computational work has gradually been producing a paradigm shift in philosophy of science, especially in the linguistic-analysis tradition. But if computational analysis is not fully embraced as the cutting edge in academic philosophy of science due to philosophers’ intellectual lethargy, then the mechanization agenda will be taken over by currently contributing cognitive psychologists.
This book has its origins in my independent philosophical reflections during and especially after my thirty months in the graduate school of philosophy at the University of Notre Dame, South Bend, Indiana. Having received a Masters degree in economics I had anticipated that my doctoral dissertation in philosophy would set forth a computerized discovery system simulating the Keynesian revolution in economics. 1980 Nobel-laureate econometrician Lawrence Klein’s Keynesian Revolution (1947) indicated the proposal’s feasibility.
Nearly all of the mechanized discovery systems described in this book were written as Ph.D. dissertations – all, that is, but mine. Notre Dame’s Philosophy Department Chairman, a Reverend Ernan McMullin, and the faculty he has hired found my ideas scandalous. They demanded that I recant my metaphysical realist philosophy (See BOOK I, Section 3.36). After initiating a denial that he wants “to play God”, this Reverend Chairman questioned my seriousness, accused me of a “bad attitude”, threatened that if I persisted in my ideas I could never succeed with his faculty, and issued his ultimatum: get reformed or get out. I got out.
I then undertook development of my computerized METAMODEL discovery system at San Jose City College in San Jose, California while taking nondegree coursework in applied numerical methods in FORTRAN. In less than a year I had successfully completed the system, and had simulated the discovery that was the Keynesian revolution in the history of economics. Afterwards I published the findings in my monograph Introduction to Metascience: An Information Science Approach to Methodology of Scientific Research.
For more than thirty years I applied my discovery system occupationally as a research econometrician in both business and government. My work in economic analysis and strategic planning during those years occasioned my evolution from a romantic neoclassical economist into a pragmatic Institutionalist economist, an evolution enabled by my discovery system and vindicated by its practical achievements. My discovery system made my research career an exciting and successful exploratory empiricist adventure while providing an economic benefit for my several satisfied employers and clients.
Contemporary pragmatists shun undecidable disputations such as those demanded by the Notre Dame philosophers. The contemporary pragmatist philosophy of science is consequential for the practice of basic research in empirical science, and computational philosophy of science enhances this enabling effectuality. In 1976 I applied my discovery system to sociologically relevant longitudinal data describing the history of the American national society for the period 1920 through 1972. In that same year the U.S. Commerce Department had published the needed longitudinal data in its Historical Statistics of the United States. My discovery system developed a quantitative post-classical functionalist macrosociometric model describing the stability conditions, patterns of interinstitutional interaction, and outcomes of institutional change in the American national society during the mid-fifty years of the twentieth century.
I then wrote a paper describing the discovery-system-generated macrosociometric model, and submitted it from 1978 through 1982 to four peer-reviewed sociological journals, namely Sociological Methods and Research, American Journal of Sociology, American Sociological Review and Social Indicators Research. All four journals rejected the paper. “Appendix I” in BOOK VIII is the submitted paper describing the model and its findings. “Appendix II” relates the referees’ criticisms together with the editors’ rejection letters and my rejoinders. Appendix III is my critique of the peer-reviewed sociology literature.
These issues are larger than between a single writer and his critics, or they could just be dropped. The referee criticisms are an exposé of academic sociology’s institutionalized retardation. Unsurprisingly the Swedish Royal Academy still does not view sociology as having