A Companion to Arthur C. Danto. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Arthur C. Danto - Группа авторов страница 40

A Companion to Arthur C. Danto - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

in his work, and which they see as leading him to posit a metaphysical dualism of mind and body. Such a phenomenological approach would construe epistemic privilege as a kind of privileged access that is afforded by consciousness. Bilgrami eschews all questions about how self-knowledge is afforded, and fastens exclusively on the normative point that self-knowledge is a condition on the kind of agency that is possessed by reflective subjects with a first-person point of view. His eschewal of the how question is a striking point of convergence with Danto’s claim that agents do not know, and moreover do not need to know, how they are able to perform basic actions. Yet, there is also an important difference. Danto seems to just plunk it down as a brute fact about agents, that they have no idea how they are able to perform basic actions. In contrast, Bilgrami situates his convergent point, that agents have no idea how they know their own thoughts, in a systematic account that explains the distinctive nature of self-knowledge by putting it into perspicuous relation to the distinctive nature of what is self-known – which is thought, construed not as causal dispositions to behave, but rather as irreducibly normative commitments.

      3 Agents’ Powers

      Danto would surely be right to insist that the first-person point of view from which mental agency is exercised, by undertaking irreducibly normative commitments, must also be a first-person point of view from which embodied agency is exercised so as to effect changes in the world. He would be right to insist, as well, that no account of the distinctive nature of the first-person knowledge that agents possess can be complete unless it includes an account of agents’ knowledge of their powers to act. So the question arises, what would it be to try to make sense of agents’ first-person knowledge of their powers to act in normative terms? Levi’s definition of an option suggests an answer to this question.

      According to Levi, to face an option is to have a certain kind of first-person belief: I face an option to perform a certain action X just in case I believe that if I choose X then X will be done (it is implicit in this belief that X will be done by me, of course – it is, after all, a first-person belief). Levi’s interest in choice is an interest in rational choice, and the rational thing to do in his view is to choose the option that emerges to be best in the light of all of one’s commitments – best, that is, in the light of all of one’s beliefs about what is true and good, where these beliefs include one’s beliefs about what one will do if one chooses it (one’s options). Levi does not think we need a philosophical account of how a choice is efficacious, any more than Bilgrami thinks we need a philosophical account of how we come to possess self-knowledge of our commitments, or Danto thinks we need a philosophical account of how we are able to perform basic actions directly at will. Levi holds that it suffices to register what agents think, from their own first-person points of view, in the course of exercising their agency. In his view, to register this is to register the normative basis from which agents self-knowingly deliberate, choose, and act.

      Danto sets aside the issue of choice. He wants to make sense of how willing can be located within actions themselves, and so need not be preceded by any separate mental act such as choice or intention. It is a perfectly good goal to try to make sense of this idea – an idea that is sometimes put by saying that intending is in the doing. Nevertheless, it seems to me that the kind of first-person knowledge of our powers to perform basic actions that Danto attributes to us must in some sense be conditional knowledge – knowledge that we will perform the actions if we will them. For it is not as though the power to perform such actions drives us to perform them all the time, and when we are not performing them we know that it lies within our power to perform them in certain conditions. This is part of what Levi is getting at when he defines options in the way that he does – they are things we will do if we choose to do them. To some extent, we can make sense of such conditionality without bringing in an explicit act of choice, as follows: my knowledge that I can perform a certain kind of action is a belief that I will perform it insofar as I think it is called for by the circumstances in which I find myself, where to think it is called for is precisely to will it in the weak sense of recognizing that it is worth doing. In such a case, there would be no separation between willing and doing – my actions would literally be informed by thoughts, in the form of beliefs about what difference they make in the world, and about the worth of that difference.

      Danto does not regard this as a merely subsidiary, how-to, question, but rather as a question of philosophical significance – a significance that I will continue to probe in the next section.

      4 The First-Person Point of View and Embodiment

      Danto conceives an agent’s own body as that through which it performs basic actions; it is what falls within its direct intentional control when it performs actions just like that, at will. The agent can exert intentional control over other things in the world, too, by performing non-basic actions, but then its intentional control is merely indirect, a matter of producing causal effects in the world via the more direct form of intentional control that it has over its own body. Since basic actions are performed from a first-person point of view, the body, as Danto defines it is very much owned – it belongs to me, the agent who possesses it, as my body. This is of a piece with Danto’s point that to be an agent, and to possess a body, goes together with recognizing a basic metaphysical duality between the me and the not-me.

      Recall that Danto raises a problem of other bodies, which he compares to, but also distinguishes from, the problem of other minds. Both problems are alleged to arise because we must conceive others in terms of what we can know only from our own first-person points of view. In the case of consciousness, the thought is that there is something it is like to be aware of my own feelings, experiences, etc., and I can never directly confirm that there is something it is like for others too – for all I know, they are mere zombies for whom there is nothing it is like at all. The parallel problem about other bodies would be that I know from my own case what it is to have a body in Danto’s sense, of possessing a repertoire of basic actions, but I can never directly confirm that others possess a body in this sense – for all I know, their movements are mere events and not actions at all.

      The normative orientation that Levi, Bilgrami, and I all share does not give rise to any parallel problem about other agents. It does recognize a sharp distinction between the first-person point of view from which agents deliberate and act, vs. the third-person point of view of observation and prediction. But the former is not a point of view that generates so-called privacy. Agents’ capacity to conceive others as agents as being like themselves, in the respect of possessing the first-person point of view of agency, goes hand in hand with a social capacity to engage other agents from within the space of reasons in distinctively interpersonal ways, such as argument, conversation, criticism, etc. Agents cannot consistently engage others in these ways while raising a doubt about whether others are agents in the normative sense.

Скачать книгу