This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter страница 27

This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter

Скачать книгу

Are we ever directly aware of objects in the external world? Let's look at two contrasting views on the nature of perceptual experience.

      2.27 Second, on the rival indirect realist view, the answer is “no.” When we see a cup of coffee, say, we are aware of the cup but only indirectly. The IOA is something else. In experience, we are only ever directly aware of sense data, and no ordinary material object (OMO) is ever identical to sense data. The properties of the sense data determine the conscious character of your experience. It is by being directly aware of sense data that we're made indirectly aware of external objects (e.g. cups of coffee, tables, friends, etc.). Think of the way that, say, you're aware of a deer by being more immediately aware of its tracks, aware of incoming aircraft by being more immediately aware of blips on the radar screen, or aware of an intruder by being more immediately aware of the dog's barking. The indirect realist proposes that in every case of conscious experience (veridical – in other words, accurate – perceptual experience, illusion, hallucination) the IOA and its properties wholly determine what the conscious experience is like and then make us indirectly aware of external things if they are there and suitably related to us (e.g. by causing us to undergo certain experiences).

      2.29 The main point of difference between the naïve and indirect realists is over the truth of direct realism:

      Direct realism: it is possible for a subject to be immediately aware of an ordinary external object and its properties.

      The naïve realist thinks that the ordinary case of seeing a tomato shows us that direct realism is correct. The indirect realist thinks that the ordinary case of seeing a tomato shows us that it's false. This disagreement is a disagreement about the mind. It's not really an epistemological disagreement. (Notice that in stating the point of contention, we didn't use normative concepts [e.g. good/bad, right/wrong, reasonable/unreasonable] and didn't mention knowledge.) Why should it concern epistemologists?

      2.30 It should concern epistemologists because debates about what we can and cannot be immediately aware of interact with debates about we can and cannot rationally believe or know. It also interacts with more fine‐grained debates about how we can rationally believe or know (e.g. whether we need evidence over and above our experiences to believe certain things).

       An Argument against Liberal Foundationalism

      P1. If direct realism is false, we are never immediately aware of anything external to the mind.

      P2. If we are not immediately aware of something external to the mind, we cannot rely on experience alone to justifiably believe that such things exist or that such things have certain properties.

      C1. So, if direct realism is false, we cannot rely on experience alone to justifiably believe that such things exist or that such things have certain properties.

      P3. If liberal foundationalism is correct, we can rely on experience alone to justifiably believe that external things exist and have certain properties.

      C2. So, if direct realism is false, liberal foundationalism is mistaken.

      This kind of reasoning supports the idea that we cannot have justified beliefs from experience on its own to believe in things that we're only made aware of indirectly when we have an experience. Think about the blips on the radar screen. If you're aware of them but have no good independent reason to believe that these blips correlate with incoming aircraft, you cannot justifiably believe that aircraft are coming in just by seeing the blips. If you're aware of smoke but don't justifiably believe that smoke correlates with fire, you cannot justifiably believe that there's a fire.

      2.32 We don't take this kind of argument to be decisive. However, if this argument is sound, it's quite troubling. Not every foundationalist is a liberal foundationalist. There is a traditional foundationalist view that tries to account for knowledge about the external world inferentially. On such views, you might come to know via inference that a tomato exists or that it's red by basing these beliefs on more basic beliefs about your own mental life. One difficulty that such views face is that the proponents of these views either need to identify some kind of evidence that connects these kinds of beliefs or explain why such evidence isn't needed. It's difficult to see, for example, how experience alone could give us the evidence we need to connect these two kinds of beliefs. If we don't have direct experience, say, of tomatoes and their color, we don't have direct experience of how these entities correlate with the experiences we have that lead us to believe that tomatoes are present. If the best option for the foundationalist is liberal foundationalism, it's important for the foundationalists to find some way of responding to this argument.

      2.34 Critics of naïve realism claim that certain familiar facts about experience show that we're never immediately aware of any external objects. If you conceive of the experience a subject has when, say, she sees the pages before her as nothing but a relation between a perceiver and the pages before her, you might be attracted to this kind of naïve explanation of the present character of your experience:

      

Скачать книгу