The Forgetting: Understanding Alzheimer’s: A Biography of a Disease. David Shenk

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Forgetting: Understanding Alzheimer’s: A Biography of a Disease - David Shenk страница 10

Автор:
Серия:
Издательство:
The Forgetting: Understanding Alzheimer’s: A Biography of a Disease - David  Shenk

Скачать книгу

was a perfect case of anterograde amnesia, the inability to store any new memories. Persons with incipient Alzheimer’s disease exhibit a slightly less severe form of the same problem. The memory of leaving the car keys in the bathroom isn’t so much lost as it was never actually formed.

      In a healthy brain, sensory input is converted into memory in three basic stages. Before the input even reaches consciousness, it is held for a fraction of a second in an immediate storage system called a sensory buffer.

      Moments later, as the perception is given conscious attention, it passes into another very temporary system called short-term (working) memory. Information can survive there for seconds or minutes before dissolving away.

      Some of the information stirring in working memory is captured by the mechanism that very slowly converts into a long-term memory lasting years and even a lifetime.

      Long-term memories can be either episodic or semantic. Episodic memories are very personal memories of firsthand events remembered in order of occurrence. Before the baseball game the other day, I put on my new pair of sneakers, which I had gotten earlier that morning. Then we drove to the stadium. Then we parked. Then we gave the man our tickets. Then we bought some hot dogs. Then we went to our seats …

      Now, days later, if I notice a mustard stain on my shoe, I can plumb my episodic memory to determine when and how it happened. If my feet start bothering me, my episodic memory will help me figure out whether it happened before or after I bought my new shoes.

      Semantic memories are what we know, as opposed to what we remember doing. They are our facts about the world, stored in relation to each other and not when we learned them. The memory of Neville Chamberlain’s “peace in our time” is semantic.

      They are separate systems—interrelated, but separate. An early-stage Alzheimer’s patient who cannot retain memories of where she put her keys has not forgotten what keys are for, or what kind of car she drives. That will come much, much later, when she starts to lose old semantic memories.

      The experience with H.M. taught researchers that the hippocampus is key to long-term memory formation. Without that tiny organ, he was totally incapable of forming new, lasting memories. Alzheimer’s patients suffer the exact same systemic loss, but over several years rather than one surgical afternoon. For H.M., there were no new memories after 1953, period. In later years, he was unable to recognize his own face in the mirror. Real time had marched on, 1955 … 1962 … 1974, but as far as he was concerned, he was still twenty-five years old. If you are a young man, alert and intelligent, and you look into an ordinary mirror only to discover the face of a sixty-year-old perfectly mimicking your expressions, perhaps only then do you know the real meaning of the word horror. Fortunately, the extreme distress H.M. suffered during such world-shattering incidents was always immediately and completely forgotten as soon as his attention could be distracted by something happening in the new moment. Not remembering can sometimes be a great blessing.

      The discovery of hippocampus-as-memory-consolidator was critical. What memory specialists have been trying to figure out ever since then is, once formed, where do these long-term memories actually reside? Are memories stored up in the front of the brain in the prefrontal cortex? On top, in the parietal lobe? In the brainstem at the base of the brain? Where?

      One tantalizing theory emerged in the late 1950s: memories were everywhere, stored in discrete molecules scattered throughout the brain. A stampede to confirm this notion was set off by a 1962 Journal of Neuropsychiatry article, “Memory Transfer Through Cannibalism in Planaria,” in which the University of Michigan’s James McConnell eagerly reported that worms could capture specific memories of other worms simply by eating those worms. McConnell had trained a group of flatworms to respond to light in a noninstinctive way. He then killed these worms, chopped them up, and fed them to untrained flatworms. After eating their brethren, McConnell claimed, the untrained worms proceeded to behave as though they had been trained—they had somehow acquired the memory of the trained worms. It was the unexpected apotheosis of the old saying, “You are what you eat.”

      Out of this report numerous research grants were born, some of which yielded tantalizing results. Three years after McConnell’s initial study, four California scientists reported in the journal Science that when cells extracted from the brains of trained rats were injected into the guts of untrained rats, the untrained rats picked up the learned behavior of the trained rats. These experiments apparently showed that specific, concrete individual memories were embedded as information in discrete molecules in the same way that genetic information is embedded in DNA, and that these memories were transferable from brain to brain. A later experiment by Baylor University’s Georges Ungar was the most vivid yet: Brain cells from rats that had been trained to fear the dark were transferred to untrained mice (ordinarily, neither mice nor rats fear the dark), who suddenly took on this new fear. Ungar even isolated a peptide comprising fifteen amino acids that he said contained the newly created memory. He called the transmissible fear-of-the-dark memory molecule scotophobin.

      The theory that emerged out of these experiments was of memory as a distinct informational molecule that could be created organically in one brain, isolated, and then transferred to another brain—even to the brain of another species. Its implications were immense. Had this cold fusion of an idea been validated rather than widely discredited not long after Ungar’s paper was published in Nature in 1972, it is clear that ours would be a very different world today: Memory swaps. Consciousness transfers. Neurochemical behavioral enhancements that would make Prozac seem like baby aspirin. The rapid decoding of a hidden science of memory molecules might well have spawned a new type of biochemical computer that could register, react to, and even create memory molecules of its own. Laptops (or cars or stuffed animals) could be afraid of the dark or partial to jazz or concerned about child abuse. Memories and feelings could be bottled and sold as easily as perfume.

      But that world did not, and cannot, emerge. The memory transfer experiments, while entertaining and even seductive—DNA pioneer Francis Crick was among the many prestigious scientists on board for a while—were ultimately dismissed as seriously misguided). The idea of transferable memories strained credulity to begin with; to suggest that one animal’s specific fear could travel through another animal’s digestive tract, enter its bloodstream, find its way to the brain, and turn itself on again in the new host mind was an even further stretch.

      And then there was the problem of physical mass. Skeptics calculated that if specific memories were contained in molecules the way Ungar suggested, the total number of memories accumulated over a lifetime would weigh somewhere in the vicinity of 220 pounds. The brain would literally be weighed down by thought and ideas.

      After a decade or so, the notion and burgeoning industry of memory molecules crumbled into dust. It is now one particularly humiliating memory that many neuroscientists would just as soon not retain. What has grown up out of that rubble over the last thirty years is a very different understanding of memory—not as a substance but as a system. Memories are scattered about; that part the memory molecularists had right. Memory is everywhere. But it is everywhere in such a way that it is impossible to point to any one spot and identify it with an explicit memory. We now know that memory, like consciousness itself, isn’t a thing that can be isolated or extracted, but a living process, a vast and dynamic interaction of neuronal synapses involved in what Harvard’s Daniel Schacter elegantly terms “a temporary constellation of activity.” Each specific memory is a unique network of neurons from different regions of the brain coordinating with one another. Schacter explains:

      A typical incident in our everyday lives consists of numerous sights, sounds, actions, and words. Different areas of the brain analyze these various aspects of an event. As a result, neurons in the different regions become more strongly connected to one another. The new pattern of connections constitutes the brain’s record of the event.

      The

Скачать книгу