The Poetics of Aristotle - The Original Classic Edition. Aristotle Aristotle
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу The Poetics of Aristotle - The Original Classic Edition - Aristotle Aristotle страница 1
THE POETICS OF ARISTOTLE By Aristotle
A Translation By S. H. Butcher
[Transcriber's Annotations and Conventions: the translator left intact some Greek words to illustrate a specific point of the original discourse. In this transcription, in order to retain the accuracy of this text, those words are rendered by spelling out each Greek letter individually, such as {alpha beta gamma delta...}. The reader can distinguish these words by the enclosing braces {}. Where multiple words occur together, they are separated by the "/" symbol for clarity. Readers who do not speak or read the Greek language will usually neither gain nor lose understanding by skipping over these passages. Those who understand Greek, however, may gain a deeper insight to the original meaning and distinctions expressed by Aristotle.]
Contents
Analysis of Contents
ARISTOTLE'S POETICS I
II III IV V
VI VII VIII IX
X XI
XII XIII XIV
XV XVI XVII XVIII XIX XX XXI XXII
XXIII XXIV
1
XXV
XXVI
'Imitation' the common principle of the Arts of Poetry. The Objects of Imitation.
The Manner of Imitation.
The Origin and Development of Poetry.
Definition of the Ludicrous, and a brief sketch of the rise of
Comedy.
Definition of Tragedy.
The Plot must be a Whole.
The Plot must be a Unity.
(Plot continued.) Dramatic Unity.
(Plot continued.) Definitions of Simple and Complex Plots. (Plot continued.) Reversal of the Situation, Recognition, and Tragic or disastrous Incident defined and explained.
The 'quantitative parts' of Tragedy defined.
(Plot continued.) What constitutes Tragic Action.
(Plot continued.) The tragic emotions of pity and fear should spring out of the Plot itself.
The element of Character in Tragedy.
(Plot continued.) Recognition: its various kinds, with examples. Practical rules for the Tragic Poet.
Further rules for the Tragic Poet.
Thought, or the Intellectual element, and Diction in Tragedy. Diction, or Language in general.
Poetic Diction.
(Poetic Diction continued.) How Poetry combines elevation of language with perspicuity.
Epic Poetry.
(Epic Poetry continued.) Further points of agreement with Tragedy. Critical Objections brought against Poetry, and the principles on which they are to be answered.
A general estimate of the comparative worth of Epic Poetry and Tragedy.
ARISTOTLE'S POETICS
I
I propose to treat of Poetry in itself and of its various kinds, noting the essential quality of each; to inquire into the structure of the plot as requisite to a good poem; into the number and nature of the parts of which a poem is composed; and similarly into whatever else falls within the same inquiry. Following, then, the order of nature, let us begin with the principles which come first.
Epic poetry and Tragedy, Comedy also and Dithyrambic: poetry, and the music of the flute and of the lyre in most of their forms, are all in their general conception modes of imitation. They differ, however, from one: another in three respects,--the medium, the objects, the manner or mode of imitation, being in each case distinct.
For as there are persons who, by conscious art or mere habit, imitate and represent various objects through the medium of colour and form, or again by the voice; so in the arts above mentioned, taken as a whole, the imitation is produced by rhythm, language, or
'harmony,' either singly or combined.
2
Thus in the music of the flute and of the lyre, 'harmony' and rhythm alone are employed; also in other arts, such as that of the shepherd's pipe, which are essentially similar to these. In dancing, rhythm alone is used without 'harmony'; for even dancing imitates character, emotion, and action, by rhythmical movement.
There is another art which imitates by means of language alone, and that either in prose or verse--which, verse, again, may either combine different metres or consist of but one kind--but this has hitherto been without a name. For there is no common term we could apply to the mimes of Sophron and Xenarchus and the Socratic dialogues on the one hand; and, on the other, to poetic imita-tions in iambic, elegiac, or any similar metre. People do, indeed, add the word 'maker' or 'poet' to the name of the metre, and speak of elegiac poets, or epic (that is, hexameter) poets, as if it were not the imitation that makes the poet, but the verse that entitles them all indiscriminately to the name. Even when a treatise on medicine or natural science is brought out in verse, the name of poet is by custom given to the author; and yet Homer and Empedocles have nothing in common but the metre, so that it would be right to call the one poet, the other physicist rather than poet. On the same principle, even if a writer in his poetic imitation were to combine all metres, as Chaeremon did in his Centaur, which is a medley composed of metres of all kinds, we should bring him too under the general term poet. So much then for these distinctions.
There are, again, some arts which employ all the means above mentioned, namely, rhythm, tune, and metre. Such are Dithyrambic and Nomic poetry, and also Tragedy and Comedy; but between them the difference is, that in the first two cases these means are all employed in combination, in the latter, now one means is employed, now another.
Such, then, are the differences of the arts with respect to the medium of imitation.
II
Since the objects of imitation are men in action, and these men must be either of a higher or a lower type (for moral character mainly answers to these divisions, goodness and badness being the distinguishing marks of moral differences), it follows that we
must represent men either as better than in real life, or as worse, or as they are. It is the same in painting. Polygnotus depicted men as nobler than they are, Pauson as less noble, Dionysius drew them true to life.
Now it is evident that each of the modes of imitation above mentioned will exhibit these differences, and become a distinct kind in imitating objects that are thus distinct. Such diversities may be found even in dancing, flute-playing, and lyre-playing. So again in language, whether prose or verse unaccompanied by music. Homer, for example, makes men better than they are; Cleophon as they are; Hegemon the Thasian, the inventor of parodies, and Nicochares, the author of the Deiliad, worse than they are. The same thing holds good of Dithyrambs and Nomes; here too one may portray different types, as Timotheus and Philoxenus differed in representing their Cyclopes. The same distinction marks off Tragedy