Never Let A Serious Crisis Go to Waste. Philip Mirowski

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Never Let A Serious Crisis Go to Waste - Philip Mirowski страница 11

Never Let A Serious Crisis Go to Waste - Philip  Mirowski

Скачать книгу

consideration relevant to our current conundrum, namely, the issue of whether most people who may subscribe to something like neoliberalism actually understand it to be constituted as a coherent doctrine with a spelled-out roster of propositions, or instead treat their notions as disparate implications of other beliefs. As we have already intimated, many people still have no clue what neoliberalism is, much less harbor opinions about how their own thought processes might relate to it. In other words, how could they come to reject something which for them putatively lacks spatio-temporal solidity, or at minimum, must they themselves consciously understand their beliefs as part of a coherent intellectual tradition?

      This volume is dedicated to exploring the ways in which the crisis has not yet served as an exemplary instance of falsification of much of anything; it explores various defense mechanisms of critical groups such as orthodox economists and members of the Neoliberal Thought Collective; the intention is to clear a path to some potential remedy to that situation. However, in order to reach that point, it is first necessary to become better acclimatized to the notion that a burst of bad news does not generally bring a dogma crashing down of its own accord. It takes a whole lot more than that; and thus a preliminary admonition of epistemic caution is the touchstone of the current chapter. The rest of this section is devoted to a quick sketch of the sobering lessons of social psychology for the premature expectations of the demise of neoliberalism; whereas the next section is devoted to the difficult question of whether neoliberalism could or should be considered a tolerably coherent phenomenon that has exhibited sufficient integrity over past decades for any refutation to have something to stick to.

      What happens when a seductive synoptic ideology suffers “breakage,” as our commentators have it? It would be odd if this had not been a major topic of exploration, since it speaks so directly to our images of ourselves and others. While there have been many modes and idioms in which the question has been broached, for the sake of brevity we shall describe but one: the attempt to comprehend these responses as a case study in the social psychological problem of cognitive dissonance. The father of “cognitive dissonance theory” was the social psychologist Leon Festinger. In his premier work on the subject, he addressed the canonical problem situation which captures the predicament of the contemporary economics profession:

      Suppose an individual believes something with his whole heart . . . suppose that he is then presented with unequivocal and undeniable evidence that his belief is wrong: what will happen? The individual will frequently emerge, not only unshaken, but even more convinced of the truth of his beliefs than ever before. Indeed, he may even show a new fervor about convincing and converting people.24

      This profound insight, that confrontation with contrary evidence may actually augment and sharpen the conviction and enthusiasm of a true believer, was explained as a response to the cognitive dissonance evoked by a disconfirmation of strongly held beliefs. The thesis that humans are more rationalizing than rational has spawned a huge literature, but one that gets little respect in economics.25 Cognitive dissonance and the responses it provokes venture well beyond the literature in the philosophy of science that travels under the rubric of Duhem’s Thesis, in that the former plumbs response mechanisms to emotional chagrin, whereas the latter sketches the myriad ways in which auxiliary hypotheses may be evoked in order to blunt the threat of disconfirmation. Duhem’s Thesis states that there are an infinite number of auxiliary hypotheses that may be invoked to explain why an empirical event did not actually impugn the target doctrine at risk: instead, uncontrolled factors intervened. Philosophy of science revels the ways in which it may be rational to discount contrary evidence; but the social psychology of cognitive dissonance reveals just how elastic the concept of rationality can be in social life.

      Leon Festinger and his colleagues illustrated these lessons in his first book (When Prophecy Fails) by reporting the vicissitudes of a group of Midwesterners they called “The Seekers,” who conceived and developed a belief that they would be rescued by flying saucers on a specific date in 1954, prior to a great flood coming to engulf Lake City (a pseudonym). Festinger documents in great detail the hour-by-hour reactions of the Seekers as the date of their rescue came and passed with no spaceships arriving and no flood welling up to swallow Lake City. At first, the Seekers withdrew from representatives of the press seeking to upbraid them for their failed prophecies, but soon reversed their stance, welcoming all opportunities to expound and elaborate upon their (revised and expanded) faith. A minority of their group did fall away; but Festinger notes they had tended to be lukewarm peripheral members of the group before the crisis. Predominantly, the Seekers never renounced their challenged doctrines, as reported by Festinger. At least in the short run, the ringleaders tended to redouble their proselytizing, so long as they were able to maintain interaction with a coterie of fellow covenanters.

      In a manner of speaking, the legacy of renunciation of philosophy and methodology in graduate education led much of the orthodox economics profession, and many of the denizens of the neoliberal world of think tanks and media outlets, to behave from 2008 onward in ways rather similar to the Seekers. The parallels between the Seekers and the contemporary economics profession, on the one hand, and the Neoliberal Thought Collective, on the other, are, of course, not exact. The Seekers were disappointed when their world didn’t come to an end; economists and neoliberals were convinced their Great Moderation and neoliberal triumph would last forever, and were disappointed when it did appear to come to an end. The stipulated turning point never arrived for the Seekers, while the unsuspected turning point got the drop on the economists. The Seekers garnered no external support for their doctrines, indeed, quitting their jobs and contracts prior to their fated day; the economists, and more clearly, the Neoliberal Thought Collective, persisted in being richly rewarded by many constituencies for remaining stalwart in their beliefs. The public press was never friendly toward the Seekers; it turned on the economists only with the financial collapse. (There are now plentiful signs it has been reverting to its older slavish adoration, however.) But nonetheless, the shape of the reactions to cognitive dissonance turned out to be amazingly similar. The crisis, which at first blush might seem to have refuted almost everything that the NTC and the economic orthodoxy stood for, was in the fullness of time more often than not trumpeted from both the left and the right as reinforcing their adherence to, respectively, neoclassical economic theory or the neoliberal tradition.

      In the last few years, there may have opened up a divergence between the explicit behavior of professional economists and that of other groups who may have displayed some allegiance to neoliberal doctrines. This distinction, insisted upon in chapter 1, now begins to bite. The difference comes with the economists readily accepting that they do share some common doctrines and intellectual orientations. Their PhD from a ranked institution does double duty as a membership card; few of them spend any time doubting whether “economics” as a body of doctrine exists. Thus it will prove relatively straight­forward to demonstrate that they have not revised their erstwhile doctrines dating from before the crisis. But the denizens of the think tank planisphere and journalists and political actors in these contentious times may not subscribe so intently or openly to a fixed, discrete set of doctrines in quite the same unself-conscious manner. (Indeed, ­chapter 6 will propose a stratified spectrum of crisis response under neoliberalism.) Consequently, demonstration of the fundamental premise of cognitive dissonance theory—that people don’t shift allegiances in the throes of contravening evidence—will require more elaborate documentation for the neoliberals. Once again, the imperative to treat both groups separately will prove clarifying.

      Does Neoliberalism Really Exist?

      The really fascinating battles in intellectual history tend to occur when some group or movement goes on the offensive and asserts that Something Big really doesn’t actually exist. A short list of blasts from the past would include: the earth-centered universe, God, the Philosopher’s Stone, atoms, the vacuum, the divine right of kings, perpetual motion machines, evolution, a formally complete axiomatic system, aether, global warming, society, and human consciousness. As chapter 1 noted, we have just passed through a period when a substantial cadre were insisting that orthodox neoclassical economics didn’t exist. Nothing gets the blood roiling like the assertion that we have been arguing over nothing.

Скачать книгу