The Protector Ethic. James V. Morganelli

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Protector Ethic - James V. Morganelli страница 6

Автор:
Жанр:
Серия:
Издательство:
The Protector Ethic - James V. Morganelli

Скачать книгу

Did he do the right thing?

      He saw the violence and knew it was wrong. This young lady did not deserve to be beaten by a cretin. In his gut, he knew this to be immoral and acted. Our hero, a trained martial artist, gained tactical advantage and took the bully out. Now, had the violence stopped at that point, perhaps he could’ve tipped his hat and walked into the sunset. But the question remains: Did his tactical action provide him with the best option to stop the violence and prevent more?

      Some will say yes, based on his intention to do right. But intending is not the same as doing. Knowing the right is not enough—doing the right is what counts. Then perhaps by merit of the outcome? Still not enough. The outcome could have been born of pure luck, like a rum-fueled dance-like-nobody’s-watching stumble accidentally knocking the attacker out—hardly an ethical act, even when the outcome goes his way. But the outcome didn’t go his way, and our hero was lucky he won only some nasty bruises, in spite of doing a noble, dumb thing that could have resulted in croaking at the hands of angry drunks.

      The world is a brutal place, and there will always be cases in which good folks have no choice but to attack an attacker, even at great risk to themselves or others. But this doesn’t mean it should be our first choice. In fact, if your default setting in regular training is “stomping mudholes in chests” or worse, slitting throats like a commando but you are not a commando, you are priming yourself to go off road, even off map, to cause greater conflict and violence. “Kill ’em all and let Gary sort ’em out” is an awful way for Gary to live in the real world, where some of that indiscriminate aggression will rub off on him and people he cares about.

      We can be tactical without being ethical. It’s easy, really—far easier than being both, for sure. Even though our hero had been tactical—he approached and ambushed unseen from the rear—he had not acted on the ethical first. If he had, he would have given himself the best opportunity for the outcome he was initially compelled to effect.

      Let’s remember why he intervened to begin with. It wasn’t to deliver justice to the villain and tie him up with a note for the cops. He did it to protect a young woman who could not protect herself. Why, then, did he choose a tactic that endeavored the former and neglected the latter? Bear in mind, once the aggressor’s friends attacked our hero, it created a new issue: now he needed defending. And the young woman was left in the very same predicament our hero found her in to begin with—at the mercy of those who meant her harm. He had lost touch with the duties he was obligated to uphold to himself. And if he had failed himself, what use was he to anyone else in need?

      By unnecessarily attacking the attacker, the hero placed himself, the girl, and even his attackers in potentially deadly harm. Yes, even his attackers: had the hero or someone else been carrying a concealed weapon, such as a firearm, it might have turned into a turkey shoot with no turkeys.

      What ought the hero have done?

      He should have placed himself between the young woman and her abuser and separated them. This ethical action is the best tactical action, as it protects everyone:

       By standing up for the girl, he becomes a guardian to protect her from further violence.

       By not immediately attacking the attacker, our hero protects himself because the attacker isn’t forced into a fight. Fighting becomes a choice the attacker has to make.

       It also protects the attacker from harm by the hero, as well as harm he may incur on himself as a result of his own poor behavior, even if he doesn’t realize it.

      Our hero should have acted as a protector of self and others, including, if possible, the enemy. This outlines the protector ethic, with the “if possible” as the balance, since we must engage from a sober understanding of our ability under given conditions—we can only do what we are confident we are capable of doing. Protecting our enemy is definitely the most difficult and dangerous thing we can do. It doesn’t just speak to our willingness to do it; it also speaks to our martial capability and maturity because there is no higher skill than to subdue an aggressor without killing him.

      Operating from the perspective that less is definitely more, when engaging in violence we should employ the least deadly tactic (until more lethal ones are required), in order to conform with the protector ethic. We should take the application of martial tactics as seriously as any mortal threat posed against us. The human body is a complex, if sometimes frail, vessel that can malfunction just as often as it can perform wondrous feats. How an opponent will react in response to grave techniques is often an educated guess. Every year there are an alarming number of scuffles that turn deadly—one-punch knockouts that end up homicides, and this often between untrained people. And let’s face it: any physical action we perform may land us in court, since in this polite society, litigiousness is a culling sword, even when folks follow the law and do everything right.

      Balancing the ethical-tactical continuum is the best way to increase our ability because it’s when we can (or cannot) ethically protect everyone and resolve conflict that tactics become vividly clear. The tactical itself, on its own, is devoid of meaning without orientation—a sword-cutting technique is simply that, a procedure to cut with a sword. The technique gains priority and consequence only when used in fulfilling our protector ethic, which is always moral-physical.

      Some believe the ethical and tactical are mutually exclusive, even incompatible. The tactical is about survival, they’ll say—“Kill or be killed.” The ethical is for Sunday school or philosophers, who rarely, if ever, get punched in the face. But this is hardly true—I get punched all the time.

      Anytime someone decides to begin martial training, the decision itself is of an ethical nature. Take the three most basic questions anyone who trains must answer:

      What am I going to learn?

      How am I going to learn it?

      Whom am I going to learn from?

      These considerations only gain in importance because they do not just inhabit teaching lives; they haunt them:

      What am I going to teach?

      How am I going to teach it?

      Whom am I going to teach?

      Training does not automatically moralize us just because we do it. It only grants us the opportunity, provided we affix training to its virtuous, life-protecting design. Unless students are faced with the inherent duties of the protector ethic, training is nothing but selfish endeavor. One that can become incomprehensible if we purposely obscure its path due to our own penchant for amusement, or, worse, outright refusal to follow the path where it’s taking us. The biggest concern anyone should have with training is the obsession with technical information—techniques—which

Скачать книгу