Lógos and Máthma 2. Roman Murawski

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Lógos and Máthma 2 - Roman Murawski страница 15

Lógos and Máthma 2 - Roman Murawski Polish Contemporary Philosophy and Philosophical Humanities

Скачать книгу

(1) Set theory became the fundamental domain of mathematics, in particular some set-theoretical notions and methods are present in any mathematical theory; and set theory is the basis of mathematics in the sense that all mathematical notions can be defined by primitive notions of set theory and all theorems of mathematics can be deduced from axioms of set theory. (2) Languages of mathematical theories are strictly separated from the natural language, they are artificial languages and the meaning of their terms is described exclusively by axioms; some primitive concepts are distinguished and all other notions are defined in terms of them according to precise rules of defining notions. (3) Mathematical theories have been axiomatized. (4) There is a precise and strict distinction between a mathematical theory and its language on the one hand and metatheory and its metalanguage on the other (the distinction was explicitly made by A. Tarski).

      Note also that two concepts, crucial for mathematics: the concept of a syntactical consequence (being provable) and the concept of being a semantical consequence, have been precisely defined and strictly distinguished. One could also precisely distinguish provability and truth. In a “normal” research mathematical practice – as we indicated above – they are usually identified or at least not distinguished – one says that a theorem holds, i.e. has been proved (in a “normal”, informal sense of this notion), or that it is true and treats both as equivalent and synonymous. The very process of distinguishing them was long and not so simple – cf. Murawski (2002a, 2002b). The crucial role was played here by Gödel’s incompleteness theorems.

      The incompleteness results of Gödel showed that any theory (based on a recursive set of axioms and finitary rules of inference) including arithmetic of natural numbers is in fact incomplete, hence there exist sentences that are true but are neither provable nor refutable, i.e. they are undecidable in a given theory. Before Gödel, it was believed that formal demonstrability is an analysis of the concept of ←45 | 46→mathematical truth. Gödel wrote in a letter of 7th March 1968 to Hao Wang (cf. Wang 1974, p. 10):

      [...] formalists considered formal demonstrability to be an analysis of the concept of mathematical truth and, therefore were of course not in a position to distinguish the two.

      The incompleteness theorems of Gödel belong to the so-called limitation results. They are results stating that certain properties important and desired from a metamathematical point of view (but also from the point of view of a working mathematician) cannot be achieved. Among them is the theorem of Tarski stating the undefinability of the concept of truth and the theorem of Löwenheim and Skolem showing that a mathematical structure cannot be adequately and uniquely described by a formalized theory (a theory having a model has in fact many various models). Tarski wrote (1969, p. 74):

      It was undoubtedly a great achievement of modern logic to have replaced the old psychological notion of proof, which could hardly ever be made clear and precise, by a new simple notion of a purely formal character. But the triumph of the method carried with it the germ of a future setback.

      Considerations concerning formal proofs enlightened also the role played by infinity in mathematics, in particular in the process of proving.Gödel’s results show that finite/finitistic methods of syntactical formal provability do not exhaust the variety of mathematical truth. In fact, if one wants to obtain a complete theory then some infinite/infinitistic rules (such as the ω-rule) are necessary. Recall that the ω-rule is an inference rule with infinitely many premisses, i.e. it is the following rule:

      In mathematical research practice, nobody restricts himself/herself to finite methods; on the contrary, any correct methods, among them infinite (in particular set-theoretical and semantical), are applied. Being not so ideal as it was hoped, formal proofs play an important role in metamathematics, i.e. in the study of mathematical theories or of mathematics as a collection of theories – but not only there. ←47 | 48→They enable also the automatization and mechanization of proofs in mathematics, hence they make possible the construction of automated proofs and the verification of proofs by computers. Verification of (formal) proofs is possible because the relation “x is a proof of y” is – as was shown in mathematical logic – recursive, hence effective and can be implemented. On the other hand, constructing and finding proofs is not an effective (recursive) procedure; there is no universal method of doing this (as results of Turing, Church and Gödel show). In fact, it is only recursively enumerable. Hence every formal proof is a result of a creative invention of a human being. One can say that “[f]ormalization is about checking, and not about discovery” (cf.Wiedijk 2008, p. 1414).

Скачать книгу