A Companion to Hobbes. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Hobbes - Группа авторов страница 30

A Companion to Hobbes - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

can be universal, but only that these words, living creature, stone, & c. are universal names, that is, names common to many things; and the conceptions answering them in our mind, are the images and phantasms of several living creatures or other things” (EW I.20). Such universal notions or pictures could consist in several particular ideas that we link to each other and to an abstract name.

      24 24 Hobbes seems to assume that our universal notions mirror the underlying faculties of real things. He shares this assumption with the Portuguese Jesuit philosopher, Pedro da Fonseca, and early seventeenth-century German Scholastics influenced by Fonseca’s metaphysics. Walter Sparn observes of the latter, “Their approach assumes ontologically that subtilitas [acuteness/mental penetration] is suited to experienced things, i.e., there is kinship and internal reference to God, both among things and in relation to the human intellect, by virtue of which they [things] exist in it [the human intellect] as especially representable and abstractable into general concepts. In this manner, the first principles of their knowledge can be drawn from the proportional being of things” (Sparn 2001, 481, translation mine).

      25 25 Notably, Hobbes claims that in moral science, instead of proceeding from the definitions of human will and passions obtained in physics, we can directly resolve our conception of an unjust action into “fact against law” and the notion of law into “the command of him or them that have coercive power” (EW I.74). Power will be further resolvable into the wills and passions of humans constituting the power, but these can be cognized by experience rather than demonstrated from the principles of physics. Hobbes also uses thought experiments to get clear on basic concepts, like space, possibly because simples are not resolvable. Adams draws an interesting parallel between the annihilation thought experiment in De corpore and the state of nature device to reveal the concept of equality (Adams 2019, 9–11).

      26 26 It is, admittedly, less clear how one would deduce natural laws using this particular method. This requires more research.

      27 27 Nor is analysis2 a resolution into universal notions since a medium and sentient body are both more specific than matter in general. However, it loosely resembles strict analysis in that it distinguishes something complex into parts.

      GEOFFREY GORHAM

      While Hobbes’s Natural Philosophy and First Philosophy are indebted to many sources, including fellow travelers (like Bacon and Galileo), late Aristotelians (like Zabarella and the Coimbra Commentators), and the Greeks themselves (like Aristotle and the Epicureans), the Stoic influence is not yet fully clear. To be sure, the impact of Classical and Renaissance Stoicism and Epicureanism upon Hobbes’s political philosophy has been well documented (Springborg 2010; Tuck 1983). But the Stoic roots of his science and metaphysics have not been so thoroughly investigated. This imbalance is especially worth correcting since the Stoics and Hobbes both aimed to unify all the branches of knowledge. And as thoroughgoing materialists, they both endeavored to find a place for the apparent “incorporeals”, space, time, causality, and God. One option was simply to deny the reality of these beings, and indeed Hobbes has often been characterized as an idealist about space and time, a subjectivist about the causal connection, and an atheist about God. But such characterizations are problematic insomuch as space, time, causality, and God all play important roles in Hobbes’s decidedly realist program in natural philosophy. We can better appreciate the subtlety of Hobbes’s metaphysics and science by tracing its Stoic pedigree.

      The brief first part of this chapter identifies three main sources of the Stoic elements in Hobbes’s philosophy: the early Christian-Stoic Tertullian, the modern “Neo-Stoic” school of Justus Lipsius, and the natural philosophers of the Cavendish Circle he frequented. The longer second part explores in detail the Stoic character of Hobbesian space, time, causality, and God, especially as these notions are employed in his natural philosophy. We shall see that Hobbes’s metaphysical views, though quite unorthodox in his day, served to buttress his overall materialist, empiricist, and mechanist program in natural philosophy.

      2.1 Stoic Sources

      2.1.1 Tertullian

      2.1.2 Neo-Stoicism

Скачать книгу