A Companion to Modern and Contemporary Latin American and Latina/o Art. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Modern and Contemporary Latin American and Latina/o Art - Группа авторов страница 36

A Companion to Modern and Contemporary Latin American and Latina/o Art - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

we/Who desired to prepare the soil for kindness/Could not ourselves be kind” (Brecht 1962, p. 231). Nor would have he understood how Louis Aragon, having become estranged from his surrealist comrades, could have gone so far as to praise the rule book prepared by the Union of Soviet Writers: “Missing just one of the elements required of the writer by socialist realism is enough for the work to lose its socialist realist nature, to become reduced to naturalism, to populism, to sociological vulgarization – to ruin, ultimately, its nature as a work of art” (Aragon 1952, p. 409). Rather, it is reasonable to assume that Mariátegui would have applauded the famous formula laid out in the manifesto “Towards a Free Revolutionary Art” (1938), as it appears in the version revised by Trotsky:

      From Mariátegui's perspective, art is politically relevant as long as it preserves its creative independence. When art is no longer an end and rather becomes an instrument, it abandons its core mission: challenging the conventional wisdom of the establishment.

      It might be observed, in hindsight, that Mariátegui's firm belief in the sovereignty of art bears the mark of a long‐gone, more innocent era, one in which the communist revolution existed in a kind of eternal dawn: more than a fait accompli, revolution was in fact a hope, and more than a reality to protect, it was a goal to achieve. Here we are talking about a time when the tradition of revolutionary Marxism had not yet succumbed to the fetish of armed struggle, a time before the Soviet Union had polarized intellectuals across the globe, becoming the ultimate litmus test for determining who was for and who was against the revolution. Against this backdrop one could say – if Mariátegui is read with the characteristic hardheadedness of the apparatchik – that his passionate plea for artistic creativity was a luxury that only those far from the centers of power and free from political responsibilities can afford. Harsh as it may be, there is some truth to this claim; Mariátegui's Marxism, as Michael Löwy (1998) has acutely observed, is a romantic one – a Marxism whose search for transcendence infuses it with distinctly mystical and religious overtones. “Neither Reason nor Science,” writes Mariátegui, “can satisfy all the need of the infinite that exists in man” (1959b, p. 18; 1994, Vol. I, p. 497; 1996, p. 142).

      At the same time, however, this mystic was not easily swayed by illusions. Let us recall, for instance, his trenchant observations about the peasant mentality:

      The peasant tide indeed seems driven by a reactionary will toward reactionary ends. The countryside loves tradition too much. It is conservative and superstitious. Its mind is too easily conquered by antipathy and resistance to the heretical and iconoclastic spirit of progress. German nationalism, like Italian fascism, does its recruiting in the provinces, in the countryside.

      (1959b, p. 46; 1994, Vol. I, p. 509)

      The city, he concludes, prepares “man for collectivism, [whereas] the countryside excites his individualism” and his desire to own land (1959b, p. 47; 1994, Vol. I, p. 510). A further indication of Mariátegui's sound pragmatism is that his own defense of the autonomy of art, regardless of its optimistic tones, is not blind to the fact that art is both an economic activity and an institutional practice. There exists, he says, an essential connection between art centers and power centers:

      (1959b, p. 81; 1994, Vol. I, p. 526)

      This most unusual combination of mysticism and materialism, of romanticism and pragmatism, leads one to wonder how Mariátegui's thought would have evolved in the years following his untimely death.

      The writings that we have discussed thus far provide us with some ground for speculation. First of all, it seems likely that Mariátegui would have adopted, sooner than later, a critical stance with regard to the Soviet regime, especially after the latter abandoned the project of world revolution. We might also suspect that he would have seen a reflection of his own ideas in Antonio Gramsci's meditations on the national‐popular as well as in the messianism of Walter Benjamin. Insofar as they elevate the ideal of the new to the rank of moral imperative, the philosophies of Ernst Bloch and Cornelius Castoriadis might have similarly drawn his attention.

      With respect to art, an issue that would have surely preoccupied Mariátegui is the crisis of the ideal of originality, the result of both the emergence of culture industries and the impact of technology on the production and consumption of art. How would he have reacted to the increasing reproduction of art on a massive scale and the resulting death of the artwork as a unique and unrepeatable object? Would he have welcomed these phenomena, as Benjamin did, because of their democratizing potential? Or would he have declared art obsolete in agreement with Theodor Adorno's pessimistic account?

      We cannot know precisely what solutions he would have offered, but by way of conclusion, we might speculate that Mariátegui would likely have been puzzled by the narrow chauvinism that underlies much “postcolonial” thinking today. Cultural difference, he believed, was not a matter of metaphysical essences or self‐enclosed identities, but of styles and individualities. His own indigenism, as we have seen, was not grounded on racial or ethnic utopias, but rather on a sense of historical justice that, anticipating Benjamin, demanded that we read history against the grain and take the side of the victims. The notion that cultures are fixed signs of identity, that they set insurmountable boundaries between that which is one's own and that which is foreign, would have made little sense to him. Although he considered himself an Indian (which he was not), he felt Gothic art to be his own. What is ours, he believed, is that which we find intelligible and valuable (1959b, pp. 73–78; 1994, Vol. I, pp. 523–525). As if it were a matter of inverting that old, worn‐out cliché according to which one can only attain universality by adhering to the particular, he was convinced that the particular could only be reached by way of the universal – that only “the universal, ecumenical roads we have chosen to travel, and for which we are reproached, take us ever closer to ourselves” (1959a, p. 305; 1971, p. 287; 1994, Vol. I, p. 157).

      Notes

      1 1 For the sake of clarity, I expound this book as if it were a treatise, even though Mariátegui does not sustain any single argument throughout its pages and each essay can be read on its own. It should be noted as well that, before the publication of Mariátegui total (1994), the essays composing The Morning Soul had already appeared in three separate volumes of the standard pocket edition of his Complete Works: El alma matinal y otras estaciones del hombre de hoy (1959b [1950]), El artista y la época (1959c), and Signos y obras (1959d). In what follows, I use the title The Morning Soul as referring to the overall content of those three volumes, thus adhering to Mariátegui's original intention. All translations are mine unless otherwise noted. Whenever existing translations in English are used, the original sources are also listed for reference.

      2 2 See Schutte (1988) and Nugent (1991), pp. 16–29.

      3 3

Скачать книгу