Natural History Collections in the Science of the 21st Century. Группа авторов
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу Natural History Collections in the Science of the 21st Century - Группа авторов страница 16
It is also important to understand that these living organisms that are still unknown to science do not only include rare “exotic” species or sisters of known species without much immediate societal interest: so-called exotic, unknown or unrecognized species remind us incessantly when we are confronted with a new “plague” or vector or pathogen for humans. For example, the recent discovery in France of exotic flatworms that have been introduced, are invasive and are predators of earthworms, leads to understanding of how much these organisms are totally misunderstood and scorned by everyone, including most scientists (Justine et al. 2018). Everyone then understands momentarily how valuable collections are and how they allow us to situate a species in relation to existing knowledge about living species in relation to taxon names.
We are therefore rather stuck in this traditional vision of collections as a matter of curiosity, repertoire and support for the study of evolution, in the narrow context of indispensable but very focused studies of taxonomy and evolution. We need to reintegrate natural history collections into more diverse scientific and societal issues by starting again from the fundamentals.
2.4. Collections: more than species catalogues
In terms of fundamentals, it is important to realize that collections are samples of living organisms that reflect not only specific richness but also genetic and phenotypic diversity among individuals. This goes against the traditional taxonomic conception that considers collections like Noah’s ark, where the list of different species is proof of their importance. In fact, the sum of natural history collections in different institutions allows us to examine many individuals assigned to different species and not to study biological diversity with a simplistic view which would consider each species as invariant. Moreover, it must be understood that the notion of species is an operational facility to designate networks of relationships between individuals whose limits are somewhat imprecise. The species is not a natural kind or individual, and each identification and assignation to a species is an arbitrary scientific decision: a species cannot be enumerated on the basis of all its constituent individuals, but extensionally (Grandcolas 2017b, pp. 116–128). Not only is this enumeration not materially feasible and would require inordinate material resources, but it would also become impossible at the margin of each species in which individuals reproduce momentarily with those assigned to other species or are themselves of indefinite assignment.
When studying biodiversity, it is therefore important or even crucial that data can be linked to a specimen, especially in the case of poorly known “species”, especially since the “species” taxon can be revised and its definition revised a posteriori, thus changing the meaning of the name and the assignment of individuals to a species group (Troudet et al. 2018).
This situation is very poorly understood by society as a whole and by a large part of the scientific community, which approaches the question of species with a very essentialist vision. In this vision, phenotypic discontinuities between species are wrongly taken as a confirmation of their reality, and attributed, without proof, to reduced gene flow. In this view, the species would evolve and be transgressed only by rare and unproductive hybridization events or by exceptional evolutionary changes. In reality, hybridization is often trivial and the species is a porous category at the genetic level; the discontinuities between species that we think we observe empirically are often a defect in the sampling of living organisms or the result of secondary extinctions, and not only the result of a splendid isolation coupled with a divergence phenomenon (Mallet 2008). Hence the importance of collections, which contribute to documenting a complex living world that is resistant to classification by multiplying the number of specimens stored, regardless of their momentary assignment to a particular taxon.
2.5. Big Data collections in space and time
Still in terms of fundamentals, specimens from collections have the great advantage of documenting a vast geographical coverage and an unparalleled temporal depth. As such, they can help answer all sorts of questions about changes in ecosystems in the context of the biodiversity crisis. Indeed, even if they were not acquired through a reasoned sampling program but erratically, as a result of various studies or opportunistic collections, the different specimens stored in museums ultimately document many different places and times and can often lend themselves to tests of scientific hypotheses formulated a posteriori (Dias Tarli et al. 2018). All global approaches with large numbers of individuals or species need this collection-resident information, though with the express condition that places and dates are accurately informed, which is not as obvious or as common as one might think. Toponyms can change or be inaccurate and even modern means of geolocation have their limits because we do not have a single exact reference ellipsoid for the whole planet.
Nevertheless, specimens in collections represent a biased sample of life on Earth, whether in terms of location, date, or taxonomic groups involved (Meyer et al. 2015; Amano et al. 2016; Troudet et al. 2017). Most of these biases are related to well-known “collector effects” (Pautasso and McKinney 2007), namely that biodiversity is best sampled in the most accessible or visited locations, and for the most societally and scientifically valuable taxa. These biases are often criticized and indeed it is often recommended that they are corrected by supplementing sampling with additional collection effort (Feeley and Silman 2011; Beck et al. 2012; Goodwin et al. 2015).
Of course, additional collection efforts are never negative, especially if they are concentrated on the most glaring deficiencies in terms of areas or taxa, since we only know 20% of all living organisms. Such efforts are often associated in people’s minds with massive data acquisition operations (large expeditions, large monographs on fauna or flora). Nevertheless, it is illusory to hope to compensate for all the deficiencies by more massive sampling. Even if there are no longer obvious large “gaps” in terms of taxa or geographic areas, the available data will still be biased with respect to the multiplicity of questions addressed or accessible, and it is therefore at least of equivalent importance to design protocols for statistical correction of these biases (Dias Tarli et al. 2018).
Rather than relying solely on a few massive operations, it is also important to consider that all published scientific studies on biodiversity should make their specimens and observations available. The accumulation of all these specimens/ observations would potentially be colossal, precisely because of the immense number of published case studies of species on diverse evolutionary or ecological issues, and would dwarf the sum of the few large expeditions conducted each year. This is not at all the case at present, and there is a real culture change to be made in this area, in the very current context of an “open science” policy (Ayris et al. 2018). This is both a fundamental ethical issue for science and an extraordinary opportunity for the community to quickly increase the amount of indispensable data on biodiversity.
2.6. What future is there for the use of collections?
Collections have the great advantage of being material and having curated samples on which all sorts of retrospective and analytical approaches can be conducted (Rocha et al. 2014). In this way, one can go back to the source data and analyze them against completely different questions than those that governed their harvest in the past. The current trend, unfortunately, is to accentuate the acquisition of dissociated observations of specimens rather than