Common Good Constitutionalism. Adrian Vermeule

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Common Good Constitutionalism - Adrian Vermeule страница 8

Common Good Constitutionalism - Adrian  Vermeule

Скачать книгу

rel="nofollow" href="#ud7359ef4-849d-567f-b188-337da03cd02c">Chapter 1. Briefly, the need for determination arises when principles of justice are general and thus do not specifically dictate particular legal rules, or when those principles seem to conflict and must be mutually accommodated or balanced. Those general principles must be given further determinate content by positive civil lawmaking. There are typically multiple ways to determine the principles while remaining within the boundaries of the basic charge to act to promote the common good – the basis of public authority. By analogy, an architect who is given a general commission to build a hospital for a city possesses a kind of structured discretion. The purpose or end of the commission shapes and constrains the architect’s choices while not fully determining them; a good hospital may take a number of forms, although there are some forms it cannot take.

      So too at the level of the whole constitutional order. The common good in its capacity as the fundamental end of temporal government shapes and constrains, but does not fully determine, the nature of institutions and the allocation of lawmaking authority between and among them in any given polity. Such matters are left for specification that gives concrete content to the operative, small-c constitution (which is not necessarily the same as the formal written Constitution even in polities that have the latter). Call this determination of the constitution.

      This agnosticism at the level of institutions, in turn, has two aspects: agnosticism about institutional design, and about the allocation among institutions of authority to interpret the constitutional scheme. Parliamentary and presidential systems, constitutional monarchies and republics, all these and more can in principle be ordered to the common good. Likewise, the common good does not, by itself, entail any particular scheme of (for example) judicial review of constitutional questions, or even any such scheme at all. The common good takes no stand, a priori, on the well-known debate over political constitutionalism versus legal constitutionalism,21 so long as the polity is ordered to the good of the community through rational principles of legality.22

      So far I have been talking about determination of the constitution. At another level, there is also determination within or under the constitution. Particular sets of institutions (among which authority has been allocated) give further specification to general constitutional principles of the common good, such as principles of solidarity and subsidiarity and others to be discussed here. Indeed, the process of determination is iterative and continues to ever-more detailed levels, as we will see. The legislature and executive, for example, may agree on a general statute giving some specification to a general legal principle, and in turn delegate to administrative agencies the authority to determine the general provisions of the statute. The agency may do so by a binding regulation, which may then require further interpretation, and so on.

      That particular interpretation of our own constitutional order, however, is separable from the general claims about the nature and principles of constitutionalism also offered here. Agreement with the general part does not necessarily entail agreement with the particular part. One may subscribe to the general framework of common good constitutional interpretation without subscribing to the full, particular interpretation of the path of American public law that I have laid out. The failure of some commentators to distinguish general claims about the nature of constitutionalism from specific claims about the determination of the American constitutional order has produced serious confusion, and one of my aims here is to clear that up.

      Throughout the book, I emphasize that courts need not be the institutions charged with directly identifying or specifying the common good. A division of institutional roles can, under particular circumstances, itself conduce to the common good. It is not written in the nature of law that courts must decide all legal or constitutional questions. The precise allocation of law-interpreting power between courts and other public bodies is itself a question for determination at the constitutional level.

      A corollary of the nature of determination is that the public authority – including the executive exercising delegated authority – may, without transgressing its boundaries, engage in what I have called “rationally arbitrary decisions.”27 Because determination involves specification within a range in which reason need not yield a unique answer, some element of irreducible judgment will be required. Should the statute of limitations for a given offense be ten years or fifteen? Or perhaps twelve? The law is not so sophomoric as to demand a first-order reason for the choice of one particular number over another, for it is impossible to give any such reason, at least within a reasonable range of choices. In this sense, reason itself allows a certain degree of arbitrary specification, which will thus not be coded as “arbitrary” in the legal sense for purposes of the common good framework.

      Libertarians and liberals find the classical tradition appalling or, worse, irrelevant. Both express, along varying lines, the fear that talk of “the common good” is just a shorthand for the preferences

Скачать книгу