Philosophy For Dummies. Tom Morris

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Philosophy For Dummies - Tom Morris страница 21

Philosophy For Dummies - Tom Morris

Скачать книгу

incoherent. There are, certainly, small areas regarding issues of personal taste and comfort where a very limited restriction of truth to perspectives seems appropriate. The statement “This ice cream is good!” might be an apt example. It could be true for you — from your perspective, given your tastes — but not for me. But that is very different from the statement, “This ice cream is three years old!” which is a standard truth claim and is not subject to relativistic restriction. Compare the difference between “It’s too hot in here” and “It’s over 90 degrees in this room.” It is the latter statement that is a better example of standard claims about reality. And it is either true or false. No relativity of perspective muddies the water.

      The complete definition of knowledge

      One necessary condition for knowledge is belief. (See the earlier section “Understanding Belief.”) A second is truth (as it is explained in the immediately preceding section). Knowledge is built on true belief. But these two conditions are not alone sufficient for knowledge. I can believe something, and my belief can be true without my actually knowing the thing believed. More is needed.

      Suppose that you were somehow to conjure up for yourself right now the belief that, at this very moment, the world’s richest man is brushing his teeth. Imagine you actually make yourself believe this, by sheer force of will, or you are hypnotized into believing it. And suppose further that, by extraordinary coincidence alone, the richest man in the world happens at this very moment to be polishing those shiny molars, nearly ready to rinse and spit. You have the belief. And the belief happens to be true. But you have no evidence of its truth. No proper connections have conveyed the truth to you. Imagine you just got lucky and happened to hold the belief at a rare moment when something was going on that made it true. Philosophers will deny that you had real knowledge of the fact stated. You did not know that the man in question was brushing. A wildly lucky coincidence of correspondence is not the appropriate attainment. Seneca (the practical Roman Stoic philosopher) pointed out a parallel situation by declaring that, “luck never made a man wise.” Luck can’t confer knowledge either. An amazing coincidence is not a connection sufficient to create something as solid as knowledge is meant to be.

      Philosophers insist that, in order for a state of belief to qualify as knowledge, there must be a real link, a proper connection, a tie of some sort like a causal chain, between your mental state of affirmation and the state of reality which makes that affirmation true. Furthermore, this link must be of the right sort to properly justify my having that belief. If I see my cat Mollie on the bed and that visual perception has caused me in normal ways to form the belief that “Mollie is on the bed,” then most philosophers will grant that my belief counts as knowledge. I don’t just believe she is on the bed; I know it.

      FAMOUS LAST WORDS: A RANDOM SAMPLE

      The difference between truth and falsehood can indeed be the difference between life and death. Consider the following statements, which, if false, in the right (or wrong) circumstances could be your last:

        “This is not as dangerous as it looks.”

        “We’re not that close to the edge.”

        “I’m sober enough. Come on, it’ll be fine.”

        “No, this is how you connect the wires.”

        “If it wasn’t safe, they wouldn’t let us do it.”

      My point? There is an absolute difference between truth and falsehood. And it matters!

      What exactly is proper justification? What counts as a sufficient reason, or as adequate grounds, for a belief to be reasonably held, and to count as knowledge? The poet Ovid advised all of us long ago, “Do not believe hastily.” And his advice was good. And we need to explore this question of justification more thoroughly.

      Truth and rationality

      

Here is the problem. Irrational belief is belief without a reliable tie to truth. So, irrational belief can be dangerous. Our natural tendency to believe is like our natural tendency to eat or drink. Not everything you come across that looks safe to eat is indeed safe to eat. Not every liquid you find is safe to drink. Likewise, not every proposition that comes your way that can look like it may possibly be true is safe to believe. Your eating and drinking should be subject to the guidance of your well-founded beliefs. So should everything else in your life. And that is even more reason for your beliefs to be subject to the careful scrutiny of reason.

      You should want to be reasonable in your beliefs because, when used well, reason can connect you more reliably to truth. It’s then important to value rationality as a road to truth, and thus to knowledge. But that means you need to know what reason is. You need to understand something about rationality and why you should value it in your ongoing quest for truth in the world.

      The prominent twentieth century philosopher Bertrand Russell wrote: “The mind is a strange machine which can combine the materials offered it in the most astonishing ways.” That comment applies well to imagination, but also to reason. Reason is just the power you have to organize and interpret the materials of your experience in the

Скачать книгу