A Companion to Greek Lyric. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Greek Lyric - Группа авторов страница 40

A Companion to Greek Lyric - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

this treatise to c.400 BC.

      55 55 See, further, Nicholson 2015. Injury might explain some of the odder athletic resumes of the victors celebrated by epinician, for example the fact that Ergoteles of Himera won as many victories at Delphi and Olympia as he did at the biennial Nemean and Isthmian games.

      56 56 E.g., Lichas, Anaxander, and Arcesilas, all of Sparta (Paus. 6.1.7, 6.2.1).

      57 57 Pausanias 6.13.9.

      58 58 The boast appears in the Damonon stele (n.21 above), for example.

      59 59 As the reconstructions reproduced in Smith 2007: 129 suggest.

      60 60 For the treatment of horses, drivers, and jockeys in Pind. Isth. 2 and epinician generally, see Nicholson 2005: 25–116.

      61 61 Astylus: Paus. 6.13.1, with Luraghi 1994: 288–304. Ergoteles: Pind. Ol. 12, Paus. 6.4.11, and SEG 11.1223a.

      62 62 Chromius: Pind. Nem. 1 and 9; Hagesias: Pind. Ol. 6, with Nicholson 2005: 83–84.

      63 63 Cylon: Herodotus 5.71, Thucydides 1.126. Cimon: Herodotus 6.103. Alcibiades: Thucydides 6.16–18. See also Kurke 1991: 171–177; Kyle 2015: 161–165.

      64 64 Aegina: Fearn 2011. Spartan hippotrophs: Hodkinson 1999: 160–165.

      65 65 Nagy 1990a: 82–115, 339–381, 413–437.

      66 66 See Herodotus 5.22, J. Hall 2002: 154–168, but also L. Mitchell 2007: 8–9, 30–31, 40–45.

      67 67 Nicholson 2011.

      68 68 B. Mitchell 1966: 108–110.

      69 69 F. Cairns 2005: 64–65, 68–70. Arcesilas: Pind. Pyth. 4–5; Arcesilas won the Pythian chariot in 462 and the Olympic chariot in 460. Diagoras: Pind. Ol. 7, which records his regular panhellenic successes in the 470s and 460s.

      70 70 C. Morgan 2007: 219–225, also Nicholson 2016a. K. Morgan 2015: 133–162 well lays out the problems and opportunities confronting tyrants after the Persian Wars.

      71 71 Telesicrates: Pind. Pyth. 9. Tenedos: Pind. Nem. 11.

      72 72 Xenocrates: Pind. Pyth. 6. Anaxilas and Astylus: Sim. 515 and 506. Ibycus’ odes: 282B and 323, with Hornblower 2004: 26–27 and Rawles 2012: 6–12, 20–25. Cf. also Pind. Pyth. 12 for an Agrigentine musician.

      73 73 See Christesen 2014: 213–221; also Young 1984: 89–176, with Golden 1998: 142–145 and Kyle 2015: 202–204.

      74 74 On Chromius, see Luraghi 1994: 338–340 and P. Rose 1974: 155–156.

      75 75 On Psaumis, see further Nicholson 2011.

      76 76 See further Nicholson and Gutierrez 2012.

      77 77 See P. Rose 1974 (on Nem. 1), and 1992: 159–163. Quotation from 1992: 163.

      78 78 Cf. the dedications of Polypeithes (Paus. 6.16.6), Anaxander (Paus. 6.1.7), Philo and his father Glaucus (Paus. 6.9.9–10.1), and the family of Diagoras (Paus. 6.7.1–2).

      79 79 Nicholson 2016a: 25–26.

      80 80 P. Rose 1992: 162.

      81 81 See further Kurke 1991: 163–256; I. Morris 2000: 187–190; Nicholson 2016a: 60–61.

       Marek Węcowski

      What, in this chapter, is meant by aristocratic culture goes far beyond the traditional scholarly focus on aristocratic ideals, aristocratic artistic patronage, and aristocratic lifestyle in all its main manifestations. Instead, it is related to a more general notion of archaic and early classical Greek culture I will try to substantiate.1 In a nutshell, I will argue that due to its universal appeal, aristocratic culture of the archaic period was a main integrative force of early Greek civilization—in both its social and its geographical dimension. Accordingly, Greek aristocracy was above all a cultural phenomenon. Meanwhile, we must start with definitions, since the very title of this essay is no longer self-explanatory.

      Defining Aristocracy

      Consequently, H. van Wees and N. Fisher praise an approach that seems more and more common in current scholarship. This approach is well represented by Alain Duplouy, who banished “aristocracy” and “aristocrats” from his ground-breaking book (Duplouy 2006). Instead, he tried to conceive a “behavioral definition” of aristocracy studying diverse mechanisms of “social recognition” of those aspiring to, or enjoying, elite status. His work focuses rather on the activities and strategies adopted in order to achieve their aim by individuals who were in constant need of negotiating or confirming their “prestige.” In their introduction, van Wees and Fisher have recourse to the notion of “leisure class” (adapted from the classical sociological theory of Veblen 1899) to denote those who not only objectively belonged to propertied social groups, but also adopted a particularly ostentatious lifestyle.

      The conclusions reached by H. van Wees and N. Fisher look entirely logical in the light of modern definitions of aristocracy that universally emphasize—with some minor variations—the hereditary nature and a high degree of exclusivity of such groups alongside their high material status (cf. van Wees and Fisher 2015: 1–2). The problem, however, lies less in our inability to find such “closed hereditary elites” in the archaic period than in the fact that these very definitions miss the point when applied to the historical realities of the archaic Greek world. To prove this, it is enough to point out that such definitions excellently fit the entire citizenry of a given political community in this period.

      Before the rise of the first Greek democratic regimes and the concomitant enlargement of the citizen-body in Athens and elsewhere to include those, who did not own landed

Скачать книгу