The Memorabilia. Xenophon

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Memorabilia - Xenophon страница 2

Автор:
Серия:
Издательство:
The Memorabilia - Xenophon

Скачать книгу

if not upon God? And if he had faith in the gods, how could he fail to recognise them?

      (2) Or, "A divine something." See "Encyc. Brit." "Socrates." Dr. H.

       Jackason; "The Daemon of Socrates," F. W. H. Myers; K. Joel, "Der

       echte und der Xenophontische Sokrates," i. p. 70 foll.; cf.

       Aristot. "M. M." 1182 a 10.

       (3) See Aesch. "P. V." 487, {enodious te sombolous}, "and pathway

       tokens," L. Campbell; Arist. "Birds," 721, {sombolon ornin}:

       "Frogs," 196, {to sometukhon exion}; "Eccl." 792; Hor. "Od." iii.

       27, 1–7.

       (4) See "Anab." III. i. 4; "Symp." iv. 48.

       (5) Or, "if his vaunted manifestations from heaven had but manifested

       the falsity of his judgment."

      But his mode of dealing with his intimates has another aspect. As regards the ordinary necessities of life, (6) his advice was, "Act as you believe (7) these things may best be done." But in the case of those darker problems, the issues of which are incalculable, he directed his friends to consult the oracle, whether the business should be undertaken or not. "No one," he would say, "who wishes to manage a house or city with success: no one aspiring to guide the helm of state aright, can afford to dipense with aid from above. Doubtless, skill in carpentering, building, smithying, farming, of the art of governing men, together with the theory of these processes, and the sciences of arithmetic, economy, strategy, are affairs of study, and within the grasp of human intelligence. Yet there is a side even of these, and that not the least important, which the gods reserve to themselves, the bearing of which is hidden from mortal vision. Thus, let a man sow a field or plant a farm never so well, yet he cannot foretell who will gather in the fruits: another may build him a house of fairest proportion, yet he knows not who will inhabit it. Neither can a general foresee whether it will profit him to conduct a campaign, nor a politician be certain whether his leadership will turn to evil or good. Nor can the man who weds a fair wife, looking forward to joy, know whether through her he shall not reap sorrow. Neither can he who has built up a powerful connection in the state know whether he shall not by means of it be cast out of his city. To suppose that all these matters lay within the scope of human judgment, to the exclusion of the preternatural, was preternatural folly. Nor was it less extravagant to go and consult the will of Heaven on any questions which it is given to us to decide by dint of learning. As though a man should inquire, "Am I to choose an expert driver as my coachman, or one who has never handled the reins?" "Shall I appoint a mariner to be skipper of my vessel, or a landsman?" And so with respect to all we may know by numbering, weighing, and measuring. To seek advice from Heaven on such points was a sort of profanity. "Our duty is plain," he would observe; "where we are permitted to work through our natural faculties, there let us by all means apply them. But in things which are hidden, let us seek to gain knowledge from above, by divination; for the gods," he added, "grant signs to those to whom they will be gracious."

      (6) Or, "in the sphere of the determined," {ta anagkaia} = certa,

       quorum eventus est necessarius; "things positive, the law-ordained

       department of life," as we might say. See Grote, "H. G." i. ch.

       xvi. 500 and passim.

       (7) Reading {os nomizoien}, or if {os enomizen}, translate "As to

       things with certain results, he advised them to do them in the way

       in which he believed they would be done best"; i.e. he did not

       say, "follow your conscience," but, "this course seems best to me

       under the circumstances."

      Again, Socrates ever lived in the public eye; at early morning he was to be seen betaking himself to one of the promenades, or wrestling-grounds; at noon he would appear with the gathering crowds in the market-place; and as day declined, wherever the largest throng might be encountered, there was he to be found, talking for the most part, while any one who chose might stop and listen. Yet no one ever heard him say, or saw him do anything impious or irreverent. Indeed, in contrast to others he set his face against all discussion of such high matters as the nature of the Universe; how the "kosmos," as the savants (8) phrase it, came into being; (9) or by what forces the celestial phenomena arise. To trouble one's brain about such matters was, he argued, to play the fool. He would ask first: Did these investigators feel their knowledge of things human so complete that they betook themselves to these lofty speculations? Or did they maintain that they were playing their proper parts in thus neglecting the affairs of man to speculate on the concerns of God? He was astonished they did not see how far these problems lay beyond mortal ken; since even those who pride themselves most on their discussion of these points differ from each other, as madmen do. For just as some madmen, he said, have no apprehension of what is truly terrible, others fear where no fear is; some are ready to say and do anything in public without the slightest symptom of shame; (10) others think they ought not so much as to set foot among their fellow-men; some honour neither temple, nor altar, nor aught else sacred to the name of God; others bow down to stocks and stones and worship the very beasts:—so is it with those thinkers whose minds are cumbered with cares (11) concerning the Universal Nature. One sect (12) has discovered that Being is one and indivisible. Another (13) that it is infinite in number. If one (14) proclaims that all things are in a continual flux, another (15) replies that nothing can possibly be moved at any time. The theory of the universe as a process of birth and death is met by the counter theory, that nothing ever could be born or ever will die.

      (8) Lit. "the sophists." See H. Sidgwick, "J. of Philol." iv. 1872; v.

       1874.

       (9) Reading {ephu}. Cf. Lucian, "Icaromenip." xlvi. 4, in imitation of

       this passage apparently; or if {ekhei}, translate "is arranged."

       See Grote, "H. G." viii. 573.

       (10) See "Anab." V. iv. 30.

       (11) See Arist. "Clouds," 101, {merimnophrontistai kaloi te kagathoi}.

       (12) e.g. Xenophanes and Parmenides, see Grote, "Plato," I. i. 16

       foll.

       (13) e.g. Leucippus and Democritus, ib. 63 foll.

       (14) e.g. Heraclitus, ib. 27 foll.

       (15) e.g. Zeno, ib. ii. 96.

      But the questioning of Socrates on the merits of these speculators sometimes took another form. The student of human learning expects, he said, to make something of his studies for the benefit of himself or others, as he likes. Do these explorers into the divine operations hope that when they have discovered by what forces the various phenomena occur, they will create winds and waters at will and fruitful seasons? Will they manipulate these and the like to suit their needs? or has no such notion perhaps ever entered their heads, and will they be content simply to know how such things come into existence? But if this was his mode of describing those who meddle with such matters as these, he himself never wearied of discussing human topics. What is piety? what is impiety? What is the beautiful? what the ugly? What the noble? what the base? What are meant by just and unjust? what by sobriety and madness? what by courage and cowardice? What is a state? what is a statesman? what is a ruler over men? what is a ruling character? and other like problems, the knowledge of which, as he put it, conferred a patent of nobility on the possessor, (16) whereas those who lacked the knowledge might deservedly be stigmatised as

Скачать книгу