Education in a Postfactual World. Patrick M. Whitehead
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу Education in a Postfactual World - Patrick M. Whitehead страница 12
Now imagine if Copernicus had said “planets moving in ellipses?—impossible!” and concluded that his perception had been mistaken. How often do students, educated in our schooling system, have the opportunity to question what they have learned? What if the planets didn’t revolve around us, but that the Earth was also in motion and revolving around some other star? Other students—the good students who do what they’re told and learn what they’re supposed to learn—would probably have laughed at him. Well, they had different methods of discouraging free-thinking back then such as banishment and house arrest. Today we use humiliation. We would brand Copernicus with a learning disorder so that nobody takes him seriously, then spoon feed him the facts of the universe in a private, go-at-your-own-pace classroom until he stops trying to understand it himself.
That’s the tyranny of fact-mindedness in a nutshell. To know something “in fact” means that it is unquestionable so don’t bother trying to understand it. This means that you must give up your own authority of understanding and entrust this to someone else: a teacher, textbook, blogger, or fake-news-reporter. See the connection? Fact-minded education has taught students to distrust their own ability to think and to problem-solve. Year after year of “it couldn’t be! Well, it must be because my teacher/textbook/news anchor said so.” The good students master this at an early age—they give up the whole project of trying to understand why 10x10=100 and just memorize that shit. Nobody is alarmed by this, because at least she will have memorized what is factual! They’re the facts she’ll need to go far in life! Nobody realizes that she has given up something far more valuable: the ability to think for herself. Now she’ll believe the fake news reports (unless, of course, someone tells her that it is fake, but even then …). So Facebook and Twitter are sanctioned because they didn’t protect their users from in-credible news sources.
The goal, once more, is to challenge the assumption that facts run the world, guide our experience, or tell us anything even remotely important. At worst, facts distract you from your own concrete experience. At best, a fact can alert you to something about your own experience. Though in the best-case scenario, it is necessary that the fact be misunderstood. This is to say that facts, when misinterpreted, can be a vehicle for understanding.
Positivism is a compelling assumption about the nature of reality for several reasons. It promises that every question has an answer, that ignorance is temporary, and that if you are equipped with the proper methods and training, you can never be taken as a fool. The deductive prowess of Sherlock Holmes, who relies on his skills of observation and logic to solve mysteries, is the hero of positivism. But perhaps more compelling than these reasons, positivism promises that with enough time, humankind will eventually develop the skills to manipulate and control the entirety of the universe (and manipulate and control we have done!).
The positivist approach has worked for many decades. It gave people a reason to continue asking important questions about meaning, why things happen, and how to make our experience better. In medicine, this model of understanding, manipulation, and control of the relationships of organic matter has nearly eliminated the threat of death by infectious diseases. In physics, the understanding, manipulation, and control of matter has led to the development of engineering, all manner of transportation devices, the utilization of energy sources, and so on. The trajectory this promises for humankind is alluring, but this doesn’t make it any less of an assumption.
The positivist assumption isn’t always helpful. Contemporary physicists have had to suspend what they “know” about the relationships between material bodies—particularly when they deal with particles that are smaller than an atom. It’s as if positivism applies to the world of atoms, but once you get smaller than this we need a new model for the universe. This is a problem when the worldview is supposed to include everything. In medicine, there are some diseases that cannot be isolated and treated. One example is the leading cause of death in the industrialized world: cardiac disease. Cardiac disease patients did not catch a bug or acquire an infection that needs to treated; they have made certain lifestyle choices that have inhibited the healthy functioning of their bodies. The food they eat, how they choose to spend their time, and the friends they keep are unsustainable. Treatment is not as easy as taking an antibiotic, and encouraging lifestyle changes in service to health isn’t as easy as it sounds.
We will first break down the term metaphysics. “Meta-” indicates that a process is being applied to itself. In psychology, for instance, “meta-cognition” means “thinking about thinking.” If by physics we mean “the rules by which the physical universe operates,” then meta-physics refers to “the rules by which we understand the rules by which the physical universe operates.” The first of these is epistemology. Epistemology is concerned with how we know what we know. For example, how do we know what a fact is, in fact? My argument, obviously, is that we don’t. A fact is itself an epistemological impossibility. Since knowledge about the universe presupposes a universe, epistemology is contingent upon ontology—the study of being. Ontology investigates the is-ness of what is. Ontology concerns the statement of being. To argue that there is a universe, and what this means exactly, is an ontological proposition. Epistemology and ontology are closely related: how do we know that what is, is? With fact-minded thinking, metaphysical questions are ignored. “Everybody knows fact a, fact b, fact c, and so on.” Understanding the is-ness of is, and the process of its discovery, are replaced by facts.
Chapter Two
The World of Facts
The tendency to reduce the universe to facts about the world is not new. Indeed, it may be traced back nearly 25 centuries to when Plato misunderstood the agreement between Heraclitus and Parmenides. “It was here,” as German philosopher Martin Heidegger has shown, “that western metaphysics began. It was also here that the forgetting of being occurred” (Seidel, 1964, p. 30). This statement should be troubling. If you’re not troubled yet, start this chapter over (it’s only a few lines).
This is the story of western metaphysics, a story that plays out today in high school integrated science laboratories, college philosophy courses, and alcohol-induced arguments around campfires. Heraclitus spoke of nature as a process—always changing. Parmenides spoke of nature as a thing—reducible to a matter of fact. In a contemporary classroom, only one of them can be correct. But in the fifth century BCE (Before Common Era), there was no argument about who was correctly using the term—there was no contradiction or ambiguity. Unfortunately, few of us can imagine this scenario: how can the propositions “a” and “not-a” both be correct? Were Heraclitus and Parmenides to have this disagreement today, both would probably defer to some “agree to disagree” bullshit, even though both would deeply resent one another for their intellectual challenge. We are deeply compelled by the idea that only one of the propositions