When Animals Speak. Eva Meijer

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу When Animals Speak - Eva Meijer страница 4

When Animals Speak - Eva Meijer Animals in Context

Скачать книгу

in a liberal democratic reality. This is relevant from a material point of view because existing institutions, rights, and practices can be changed to better incorporate animal voices, and this would make a significant difference for many non-human animals. Theoretically, it is also important to start with existing situations in order not to make universal or metaphysical claims about other animals; this would again be a matter of humans deciding what is best for other animals without consulting them. Just as with language, however, while rights and other liberal democratic institutions and practices carry a promise of justice and can make a difference for many non-human animals, one must remain critical of the system in which they are grounded, and bring to light the power relations that helped to create them. This is especially important in the case of non-human animals, who were not just excluded from rights by accident, but were seen as the “other” in relation to which “the human” was constructed (chapter 1, Derrida 2008). In order to move beyond that and conceptualize new futures, we must learn from other animals and from non-Western human cultures (Ko and Ko 2017).

      In this book, I therefore discuss existing concepts from different theoretical angles, rooted in existing practices, and explore how we can use these as tools to begin thinking and acting differently. Because thinking and acting differently will need to happen in an interspecies context, and because we do not know how other animals will act once they no longer need to fear humans, the outcome of this is unclear. As Hannah Arendt shows ([1958] 1998), this is also where we find hope.

      Political Animal Voices: A Brief Summary

      In this book, I develop a theory of political animal voices. I do so in three steps. The first part of the book focuses on language. It offers a critique of viewing language as exclusively human, as well as an alternative to that view. In chapter 1, “The Animal, What a Word! Human Language and Non-Human Animals,” I investigate the relation between language and anthropocentrism. By examing the connections between human language and non-human animal exclusion, I argue that, in order to adequately address anthropocentrism, we need to redefine language in and through interaction with non-human animals. Chapter 2, “Animal Languages,” turns the focus to non-human animal languages. In this chapter, I draw on empirical studies of animal languages and cultures to provide a better insight into their worlds as a starting point for conceptualizing interspecies interactions and world-building. I draw on Wittgenstein’s later work, and specifically on his concept “language games,” to develop an alternative way of conceptualizing and studying animal languages and interspecies languages, and I discuss different non-human animal and interspecies language games. In chapter 3, “From Animal Languages to Interspecies Worlds,” I investigate how we can conceptualize language between animals of different species, and I explore the role that language plays in constructing common worlds with other animals. The first case study, “Stray Philosophy: Dog-Human Observations on Language, Freedom, and Politics,” builds on these insights. In this case study, I draw on my personal experiences with Romanian stray dog Olli to explore philosophical concepts around three themes: language, freedom, and politics. By emphasizing Olli’s perspective and actions, I also aim to explore ways to move beyond anthropocentrism in philosophy. This case study concludes the first part of the book about animal languages and interspecies worlds, and opens the door to the second.

      The second part of this book focuses on interspecies politics; it challenges an anthropocentric demarcation of the political, and develops an alternative, which takes into account non-human animal agency and interspecies political relations. In chapter 4, “Animal Politics: Justice, Power, and Political Animal Agency,” I criticize an anthropocentric view of politics from the perspectives of justice and power relations. I investigate political non-human animal agency and discuss how non-human animal agency can function as a basis for developing new forms of interspecies politics. In chapter 5, “Animals and the State: Citizenship, Sovereignty, and Reformulating Politics,” I further explore the relation between groups of non-human animals and human political communities through a discussion of recent proposals for citizenship and sovereignty for non-human animals, and critiques from the perspective of republicanism. I also discuss examples of new ways of relating to other animals, as found in existing institutions, which can function as beginnings for further reformulating laws and political practices such as labor rights, habitat rights, and urban planning. Chapter 6, “Worm Politics,” moves the discussion to political relations between humans and earthworms to investigate the relevance of species membership for interaction, and to further clarify the borders of the political and political action. The second case study, “Goose Politics: Resistance, Deliberation, and the Politics of Space,” focuses on goose-human relations in the Netherlands. I investigate the goose-human conflict around Schiphol Airport and, based on the insights developed in the second part of this book, I argue that goose agency needs to be taken into account for normative and practical reasons. I also shed light on how goose agency can be translated to existing political practices and institutions.

      The third and final part of the book draws on the insights into language and politics developed in the first two parts to investigate how existing political practices and institutions can be extended to incorporate non-human animal political voices, and to explore new ways of interacting with other animals politically. Chapter 7, “Animal Activism and Interspecies Change,” focuses on the role of non-human animals as agents of social and political change. Acknowledging this agency is important in order not to reinforce silencing mechanisms, and can open up new ways of thinking about social and political change, as well as contributing to imagining and creating new interspecies communities. In chapter 8, “Animal Democracy and the Challenges of Political Participation,” I discuss why political participation is important for different groups of non-human animals, and how we can further improve political non-human animal participation. In the final chapter, “Deliberating Animals: From Multispecies Dialogues to Interspecies Deliberation,” I develop an interspecies understanding of deliberation in order to bridge the distance between existing dialogues between human and non-human animals and human political systems. In the conclusion, “Thinking with Animals,” I discuss thinking and writing with other animals. I also offer recommendations for further research.

Part I

      1

      The Animal, What a Word!

      Human Language and Non-Human Animals

      As cosmographers report, there have been nations that have had a dog as their king. This means that the humans in these countries had to be able to interpret canine voices and actions. According to French Renaissance philosopher Michel de Montaigne ([1595] 1958), who wrote about these nations (1958, 331), this is not really difficult to do—while it is not perfect, we have some tolerable apprehension of what other animals mean, and “so have beasts of us, much the same. They caress us, threaten us, and beg of us, and we do the same to them” (1958, 331). Non-human animals have a full and absolute communication amongst themselves, Montaigne continues, which is not limited to sounds. They also express themselves by actions, and, just as human lovers do, “speak all things by their eyes” (ibid.). Other animals also speak to humans in this manner, as humans do to them.

      Brutes are rational animals, who show justice in relations amongst each other, and to whom humans owe justice. At least they are according to the ancient Greek philosopher Porphyry, who wrote one of the first works ever on ethical vegetarianism ([268–70 BC] 1823). He wrote that reason is imperfect in other animals, but they are nevertheless not completely devoid of it (1823, Book 3). Rational capacities also differ between humans, and we should view rationality not as something you either have or do not have, but rather as something you can have more or less of. The same applies to language. When non-human animals “speak to each other, these sounds are manifest and significant to them, though they are not known to all of us” (1823, 79). This is similar for other animals—Porphyry mentions crows who understand each other, and who might see us as irrational because they do not understand all our utterances (1823, 98). Other animals do understand a lot of what we say, and they can learn from one another and from us. If we observe them for a long time, grow up with

Скачать книгу