The Crisis of Meaning and the Life-World. Ľubica Učník
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу The Crisis of Meaning and the Life-World - Ľubica Učník страница 6
I will argue that Husserl’s critique of sciences is an underlying motif from the beginning to the end of his career.8 My claim is that Husserl’s critique of natural science as he outlines it in Crisis is a continuation of his critique of “the present state of the science”9 that he first considers in Philosophy of Arithmetic. No doubt, his thinking and the focus of his critique changed, but not this principal motif: a critique of science as having become blinded by its own technical mastery rather than as a responsible practice aware of its own foundation. As he writes in Ideas III, “The sciences become [. . .] factories turning out very valuable and practically useful propositions [. . .] in which one can work as laborer and inventive technician [. . . and] from which, as a practical man, one can without inner understanding derive products and at best comprehend [their] technical efficiency.”10 Following from this insight, Husserl’s critique of science is tied to his thinking concerning the primacy of the prescientific life, or, as he calls it later, the Lebenswelt—the life-world.11 We cannot understand the world constructed by sciences unless we show that scientific explanations of the world grew out of the world in which we live; that the origin of formal knowledge is based on our experience of the life-world. For Husserl, “the world is the horizon of our total attitude” and “our belief in being is a belief in the world”;12 there is no other world than the one we live in. As Ludwig Landgrebe reminds us, for Husserl, the philosophical foundation must be based on “absolute responsibility.”13 Hence, in order to be responsible for our knowledge about the world we live in, we must acknowledge the primacy of the life-world. It is the foundation from which all our knowledge proceeds.
Husserl’s initial endeavor to inquire into the problem of meaning that underlies the possibility of knowledge, and his concomitant effort to secure knowledge from the “skeptical quagmire,” underlies his whole oeuvre. It is a journey that proceeds from investigations of mathematical concepts, through questioning the psychological basis of logic, and, later, extending his inquiries from formal logic to the problem of knowledge, as such—as when he considers the problem of “the relation of knowledge to what is transcendent” (IP, 60; italics in original); that is, the relation between our thinking and the world. Finally, he broadens his phenomenological investigations to consider the life-world.14
We might agree neither with Husserl’s claim that the crisis of the modern age is contemporaneous with the crisis of sciences, positivism, and the consequent decapitation of metaphysics;15 nor with his observation that “the crisis of philosophy implies the crisis of all modern sciences” leading to a “crisis of European humanity itself in respect to the total meaningfulness of its cultural life, its total ‘Existenz’” (Crisis, § 5, 12). Yet the foreboding he expressed is still with us. The influence of Husserl’s work reveals the relevance of his critique not only for his age but for ours as well.
What can be said of Husserl’s struggle? Aron Gurwitsch reminds us that, in 1922, Max Weber also developed a critique of science. However, “whereas Weber is prepared to resign himself to the given state of affairs, Husserl holds out the prospect of a regeneration of western man under the very idea of philosophy, into the unity of which the sciences have to be reintegrated.”16 As Husserl notes, sciences “require such criticism and grounding under the guidance of the idea of a philosophy, in which they must find their places” (FTL, § 104, 277; italics in original).
Husserl’s struggle (ILI, § 8, 45) against the disciples of psychologism, anthropologism, and naturalistic relativism is but another replay of the struggles undertaken by Socrates and Descartes. To be sure, neither historical setting nor society is the same, but the old struggle upholding the claims of reason against the general climate of skepticism seems to be unceasing. This is why Husserl, in his last work, insists:
The history of philosophy [. . .] takes on the character of a struggle for existence [. . .] between [. . .] the philosophy of naïve faith in reason [. . .] and the skepticism which negates or repudiates it in empiricist fashion [. . .] until finally the consciously recognized world-problem of the deepest essential interrelation between reason and what is in general, the enigma of all enigmas, has to become the actual theme of inquiry. (Crisis, § 5, 13; italics in original)
The problem can be stated thus: if experience, as skeptics and relativists decree, is the only basis for our reasoning, then it is difficult to see how we can explain the meaning of “what is in general,” in other words, the meaning of the world. The correlation between our reasoning and the world becomes “the enigma of all enigmas.” As Husserl mockingly puts it in The Idea of Phenomenology, “What do the things themselves care about our ways of thinking and the logical rules that govern them? They are laws of our thinking, psychological laws” (61). To put it differently, thoughts and things in the world have nothing in common. So, if we think that reasoning is “inside” us (immanent), so to speak, and the world is “outside” us (transcendent), how can we know that the things in the world are as we think they are? This puzzle can lead to a mistaken belief that “knowledge as such is a riddle” (IP, 27). This riddle contains the problem of correspondence and transcendence. Do the things in the world correspond to our knowledge of them? Or, as Husserl asks, what could it mean “for a being to be known in itself and yet be known in knowledge” (IP, 23; italics in original)? This is the problem of the correlation between our subjective thinking and the world of objects. The correspondence between our thinking and the world implies the problem of transcendence. According to Husserl, “Transcendence remains both the initial and the guiding problem for the critique of knowledge” (IP, 28). How can we know that we know the world that is outside us? For Husserl, it is phenomenology that can account for our knowledge of the world. Husserl’s many introductions to phenomenology document his unfailing belief in the ideas of truth and reason that will guide us toward knowledge.
In his review of Husserl’s Crisis, Patočka remarks that to charge Husserl with the claim that his many introductions to phenomenology prevent him from finally getting to his philosophy is to miss the point: it is to blame him for something that is implicit to his project.17 Husserl does not want to present ready-made concepts that we can use as tools, without question.18 On the contrary, he wants to show the way toward phenomenology. Husserl speaks of a “zigzag pattern” of investigation (Crisis, § 9l, 58), leading Eugen Fink to describe phenomenology as an “open system.”19 Husserl’s different investigations are paths that each of us must take in order to see “things themselves” and, in the spirit of scientific community, to contribute to the overall advancement and improvement of phenomenological investigations. As Lothar Eley remarks: “Husserl conceived of phenomenology as a working philosophy”;20 or, in the words of Maurice Merleau-Ponty, philosophy is “a continuous beginning.”21 For Husserl, the idea of philosophy is “the idea of an infinite task.”22
Not only are many researchers needed to carry phenomenological investigations forward; one’s own personal journey is also required, and this intellectual journey must be based on a constant critique of one’s own achievements. Only by traveling many paths can one grasp the idea