In the Company of Microbes. Moselio Schaechter
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу In the Company of Microbes - Moselio Schaechter страница 7
We are quite well informed about just how cells grow, and it is clear now that they do so by modeling themselves upon the existing structural framework, which is thereby transmitted to the next generation. To be sure, all the macromolecules involved in this sort of self-organization are gene-specified, but spatial order is not. There appear to be very few individual genes that prescribe dimensions, position, or orientation on the cellular scale. Instead, thanks to the ways in which cells grow, spatial cues are sometimes inherited in a manner quite independent of genes, (a well-established phenomenon known as “structural inheritance.” The form and organization of cells thus stem from two distinct informational roots: the genomic instructions that specify the parts, and the continuity of cellular architecture that guides their placement. Specified proteins and cellular guidelines operate synergistically, reinforcing each other to generate form and organization. As Rudolf Virchow might have said, it takes a cell to make a cell.
Evidence to support such a holistic view of what happens during growth is scattered, but continues to accumulate. Let’s glance at some examples. First, while many sub-cellular structures can be envisaged as products of self-construction from preformed parts, others cannot. A familiar instance is the peptidoglycan wall of bacteria, which consists of a network as large as the cell, made up of covalently-linked subunits. Enlargement during growth calls for extensive cutting, splicing, and cross-linking, even while keeping the wall physically continuous from one generation to the next. Second, even self-organizing structures must do so in a manner that ensures their correct placement in cellular space. A particularly neat example comes from recent work on the role of microtubules in cell morphogenesis of the fission yeast, Schizosaccharomyces pombe (reviewed by Martin). Microtubules define the poles of elongating cells by depositing there various members of the Tea complex, which in turn recruit additional factors. Cells of a certain mutant, orb6, grow as spheres even though they possess all this machinery. When, however, the mutant cells are grown in microfluidic channels that force them back into the cylindrical shape, the normal longitudinal orientation of the microtubules recovers, and so does deposition of polarity factors at the poles (Terenna et al.). Clearly, the microtubule system and cell form collaborate to organize the cell. Just how this comes about is uncertain, but we can borrow a clue from another admirable study, this one in Bacillus subtilis. Ramamurthi et al. found that the peripheral membrane protein SpoVM localizes to a particular patch of membrane during sporulation by recognizing its curvature; perhaps microtubule ends do likewise.
All this makes good sense, at least to me, but it reopens the question how, and indeed whether, the genome specifies cell morphology and organization. The classical conception, which has been articulated by such luminaries as August Weismann, François Jacob, and Richard Dawkins, sees the cell as a creature of its genes, and its form and functions as little more than epiphenomena. In the past, this gene-centered view of life has rested on extrapolation more than direct evidence, but confirmation has recently come by way of a remarkable paper from Craig Venter’s laboratory. Lartigue et al. described the transplantation of the entire, naked genome from one species of Mycoplasma to another, tuning the recipient into the donor by both genetic and phenotypic criteria. I hasten to add that the rate of success was vanishingly small, one cell transformed out of 150,000; that no one yet knows just what transpires during genome transplantation; and that it remains to be seen whether it can span genera as well as species. All the same, this is surely a landmark study. If one takes its conclusions literally (which the authors were careful not to do), one must infer that a cell represents the execution of the instructions spelled in its genes, and nothing more.
On the face of it, there seems to be a glaring conflict between the geneticist’s understanding of cell organization, and the physiologist’s. The former insists that form and organization obey the genome’s writ. The latter sees the genome as a key subroutine within the larger program of the cell, and it is the cell, not its genome, that grows, reproduces, and organizes itself. They can’t both be true—or can they? Note that reproduction and heredity operate on different timescales. A growing cell relies on self-organization to transmit much of its spatial order, by mechanisms quite independent of the genetic instructions. But the genes specify the parts, and mutations commonly affect the higher levels of order; on the evolutionary timescale, it will be the genes that chiefly shape cells. Having said this, there remains a long stretch between the straightforward specification of an amino acid sequence by its corresponding sequence of nucleotides, and the devious and cryptic manner in which the genome can be said to specify the whole cell. Intellectual subtleties must not obscure the conceptual shift, from a linear chain of command to a branched and braided loop of causes and effects reverberating in a self-organizing web. The only agent capable of interpreting the E. coli genome as “a short rod with hemispherical caps” is the cell itself.
There is a whiff of vitalism about this view of life, even a hint of heresy. Stop now and take a deep breath, for once you begin to wonder where all this organization came from in the first place, you are headed for the blue water.
Frank Harold is an affiliate professor in the Department of Microbiology, University of Washington Health Sciences Center. Now retired, he remains engaged with science as a writer and unlicensed philosopher.
References
Harold FM. 2005. Molecules into cells: specifying spatial architecture. Microbiol Mol Biol Rev. 69:544-64.
Karsenti E. 2008. Self-organization in cell biology: a brief history. Nat Rev Mol Cell Biol. 9:255-62.
Lartigue C, Glass JI, Alperovich N, Pieper R, Parmar PP, Hutchison CA 3rd, Smith HO, Venter JC. 2007. Genome transplantation in bacteria: changing one species to another. Science. 317:632-638.
Liu AP, & Fletcher DA. 2009. Opinion: Biology under construction: in vitro reconstitution of cellular function. Nature Reviews Molecular Cell Biology 10:644-650 (September 2009).
Martin SG. 2009 Microtubule-dependent cell morphogenesis in the fission yeast. Trends Cell Biol 9:447-454.
Ramamurthi KS, Lecuyer S, Stone HA, Losick R. 2009. Geometric cue for protein localization in a bacterium. Science. 6:1354-1357.
Terenna CR, Makushok T, Velve-Casquillas G, Baigl D, Chen Y, Bornens M, Paoletti A, Piel M, Tran PT. 2008. Physical mechanisms redirecting cell polarity and cell shape in fission yeast. Curr Biol. 18:1748-1753.
October 12, 2009
bit.ly/1LAnDEA
5