Money. Geoffrey Ingham

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Money - Geoffrey Ingham страница 6

Money - Geoffrey Ingham

Скачать книгу

‘convertible’: that is, exchangeable in an officially declared weight of gold. (Present-day British paper currency carries the anachronistic pledge ‘I promise to pay the bearer on demand the sum of [x] pounds’: that is, the sum in gold at a rate declared by the Bank of England; see chapter 4.) By the end of the nineteenth century, an increasing number of countries adopted the gold standard, which linked their currency’s exchange rates to the common standard and facilitated participation in the international trading system based in London.

      On the other hand, a minority rejected the view of the US Commission and held that money was precisely a ‘mental estimation’: that is, a socially and politically constructed abstract value (Del Mar, 1901). Soon after, in a critique of the dominant materialist conception of commodity money at the zenith of the gold standard era, Alfred Mitchell Innes concurred, declaring that “[t]he eye has never seen, nor the hand touched a dollar. All that we can touch or see is a promise to pay or satisfy a debt due for an amount called a dollar [which is] intangible, immaterial, abstract” (Mitchell Innes, 1914, 358). The dollar debt was settled by a token credit: that is, a means of payment which constituted a claim on goods offered for sale in a dollar monetary system. The existence of a debt gives money its value. As Georg Simmel explained, around the same time, in his sociological classic The Philosophy of Money, ‘[M]oney is only a claim upon society … the owner of money possesses such a claim and by transferring it to whoever performs the service, he directs him to an anonymous producer who, on the basis of his membership of the community, offers the required service in exchange for the money’ (Simmel, 1978 [1907], 177–8).

      Walker merely sidestepped the ‘incompatibility’ by smuggling the two antithetical conceptions of money into the list as different ‘functions’ of the same thing: money. After a century in textbooks, it is now widely assumed – if even given a second thought – that the differences between medium of exchange and means of payment and money and credit are semantic. Are they not different terms for the same thing? Surely, common sense dictates that handing over a coin for goods is simultaneously exchange and payment. This imagery of physical – minted or printed – money persists in the era of ‘virtual’ money transmitted through cyberspace. We shall see that digital money causes much common sense and academic confusion. Bitcoins, for example, are represented by the image of precisely what they are not: a material ‘coin’. What will be the consequences if digital money replaces cash? If money is a medium of exchange, what is ‘exchanged’ when a card is ‘swiped’ across a terminal as a means of payment? Doesn’t this rather involve the use of a token ‘credit’, carried or transmitted by the card – which is retained – to cancel a debt incurred briefly by the purchaser?

      Finally, defining money by its functions raises further questions: does something have to perform all the functions to be money? In other words, is ‘moneyness’ constituted by all the functions? For example, there are better stores of value than money. If not all the functions are necessary to confer ‘moneyness’, do any take primacy? In commodity theory, money is essentially a medium of exchange on which all other functions depend. We shall see in the following chapter that two of the functions in Walker’s list – medium of exchange and means of payment – are integral parts of two radically different theories of money. On the one hand, intrinsically valuable material commodities can become widely used media of exchange in bilateral trades: that is, bartered. On the other hand, means of payment refers to a token of credit that can settle a debt incurred by the purchase of something because the value of both credit and debt is denominated in the same money of account. The numismatist Philip Grierson illustrates the difference between medium of exchange and means of payment, which he takes to be ‘money’, with the example of fur trappers in eighteenth-century Virginia who carried twists of tobacco to be exchanged for food and lodging on their journeys. The ratio of tobacco and food and lodging varied considerably in different exchanges and the tobacco only became ‘money’ when its value was denominated in a money of account: that is, at 5 shillings an ounce (Grierson, 1977).

      A preoccupation with narrow economic functions diverts attention from a range of important questions for which the two theories also provide further ‘incompatible’ answers. First, how can money perform its functions? Orthodox economics infers that the rational individual uses money for the self-evident advantages of the functions in Walker’s list. However, these functions are only fulfilled if everyone else simultaneously sees the advantage, but this cannot be explained in terms of individual rationality. It may be rational to hold the things that fulfil the functions if they are intrinsically

Скачать книгу