Critique of Rights. Christoph Menke

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Critique of Rights - Christoph Menke страница 7

Critique of Rights - Christoph  Menke

Скачать книгу

and end”3 – into the service of “egoistic man separated from his fellow men and from the community.” The puzzle of the bourgeois declaration of equal rights is the puzzle of a self-reversal: it is the political act that authorizes apolitical human beings and thereby politics’ deauthorization of itself – the politics of depoliticization. The revolutionary declaration of rights is the first and last political act: the relinquishing of political power by means of politics – politics for the last time.

      Marx believes that “The puzzle is easily solved.”4 This solution amounts to the claim that “Political revolution is a revolution of civil society.”5 And this means that “Political emancipation was at the same time the emancipation of civil society from politics.”6 The puzzle is that the bourgeois revolution degrades political community into a means for the rights of apolitical human beings. The solution to this puzzle is the fact that bourgeois [bürgerliche] politics emancipates civil [bürgerliche] society from politics through the declaration of rights. Bourgeois politics assumes civil society as its “natural basis” and henceforth operates “on the presupposition of its existence.”7 It is governance as the administration of society. In other words, bourgeois politics is the “police.”8

      My thesis is that we cannot grasp the content, aims, and effects of the bourgeois declaration of rights without having understood how it operates. The “how” of rights has precedence over its “what,” “why,” and “to what end.” The form of rights comes before their content, goal, and effect,9 because this form is not neutral.

      Rights are a specific form of normativity: to have a right means to have a justified and therefore binding claim. And to declare a right means to grant a justified and therefore binding claim. The bourgeois declaration of rights understands this to mean that a justified claim can only be a claim as equal. That is not all, however. For at the same time, it understands this normative justification of a claim in such a way that the claim is thereby transformed into something “factual” that is prior to and separate from the political community. This holds for everything to which we have a right: for example, by giving us rights, the bourgeois state allows “private property, education, occupation, to act in their way, i.e., as private property, as education, as occupation, and to exert the influence of their special nature. Far from abolishing these real distinctions, the state only exists on the presupposition of their existence.”10 For Marx, this is the basic feature of the mechanism of bourgeois rights. Contrary to what Marx repeatedly says (and something for which he was repeatedly criticized),11 this mechanism does not consist in the justification of egoism (in general, egoism is not a category of legal theory or social criticism but rather an ethical category, a category of morality). Instead, this mechanism is the naturalization of the social (its transformation into something factual, the act of presupposing it), which happens when it becomes the content of legal claims.

      It is therefore the puzzle posed by Marx, and not his “simple” solution, that leads the way for our inquiry: it leads the way to an analysis of the bourgeois form of equal rights. As we proceed, we will have to subject liberalism to critical analysis,12 since liberalism is based on the insight that the declaration of equal rights is absolutely constitutive for the bourgeois revolution’s redefinition of politics and society. Yet, at the same time, liberalism is unable to understand that – and how – the bourgeois form of rights precisely degrades politics into the police and produces the “actual inequalities” of society. Liberalism counters the actual social and political effect of rights with its good (“moral”) intentions. This is what liberalism calls criticism, namely confronting existing conditions with good, justified claims. With this superficial notion of criticism, it skips the analysis of form. It is through form, however, that intentions produce effects.

      Marx calls this kind of criticism vulgar: “Vulgar criticism falls into … [a] dogmatic error.” It criticizes by “fighting with its subject matter.” “True criticism, by contrast, shows the inner genesis” of the things it criticizes. It “describes the act of its birth, … it explains them, it comprehends their genesis, their necessity.”13 The true analysis and true criticism of bourgeois rights are one and the same. True analysis is simultaneously true criticism because it discerns the – ontological, and not historical – genealogy of bourgeois rights. It confronts bourgeois rights not with their moral intention, but with their genesis, their basis. This means, however, that criticism is able to discover the other of bourgeois rights in their basis. According to this thesis, the basis of the bourgeois form of rights is the modern upheaval in the ontology of normativity. According to the program of true criticism, the ontological upheaval of modern law must therefore simultaneously call the form of bourgeois rights – which it establishes – into question; indeed it must undo and destroy this form. True genealogical criticism reveals a contradiction in the modern upheaval of law: it establishes and denies bourgeois law. True criticism, which proceeds genealogically, develops a radical objection to the existing conditions out of the existing conditions.

      * * *

      The way to achieve this goal proceeds in four steps that can be summarized in four theses:

      1 The

Скачать книгу