Migration and Political Theory. Gillian Brock

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Migration and Political Theory - Gillian Brock страница 15

Migration and Political Theory - Gillian Brock

Скачать книгу

direction of movement may have changed in some ways, and while there may be new powerful agencies at work, the basic problem remains the same: the global migration regime of the colonial period was a system of domination and exploitation, and the current global migration regime operates in the same way. (Cole 2011: 222)

      So once we appreciate this history, we can see that in reality, when we talk about current immigration debates, we are not really discussing just the rights that one liberal state has to control its borders. Rather, we are considering a block of powerful liberal capitalist states maintaining a system that prevents “the entry of the poor and the unskilled, while at the same time seeking those it considers economically valuable from the ‘outside,’ and maintaining more or less free movement between themselves” (Cole 2011: 222). If we consider the European Union, we see that it operates in the ways Cole suggests: there is free movement for citizens of member states and those whose skills or wealth make them attractive new members. But the poor and unskilled who seek entry will not find this easy, given the barriers imposed. In these sorts of ways, our migration regimes serve to maintain extreme inequalities in global wealth and power.

      For Cole, the unjust relationships between nations in the developed and developing world are not ones of resource inequality but rather inequalities in power. To change the fundamental injustices, we must reform “the power structures of domination and exclusion that have been sedimented through the historical processes of colonialism and post-colonialism” (Cole 2011: 222). It is primarily the inequality of power that is problematic and that has and can give rise to problematic resource distributions. So focusing exclusively on the distribution of resources rather than the distribution of power is inadequate. We must change power structures and therefore control of the global migration regime.

      In addition to this analysis and critique, he also offers a positive proposal, based on his view that there is a universal human right to freedom of international movement, “a right that is so basic that it overrides, except in extremity, a state’s right to prevent people from crossing its border” (Cole 2011: 160). He makes a case that immigration rules should become matters of international law and global governance.

      Note that Cole is not insisting that the right to immigrate be absolute. Rather, he aims to combat the situation where states need not justify their control over immigration at all or indeed any of their immigration-related decisions. Cole is proposing that the same principles that govern justification of emigration-restriction decisions could be used to justify immigration controls. In his view, such a regime would mean that immigration controls “would become the exception rather than the rule, and would stand in need of stringent justification in the face of clear and overwhelming evidence of national or international catastrophe, and so become subject to international standards of fairness, justice, and legality” (Cole 2011: 306). The system of multilateral oversight that he recommends would provide an important accountability check on states’ decisions.

      As we have seen in this chapter, two works in political theory have been especially influential in contemporary theorizing about migration. Michael Walzer (1983) defends the right of states to limit migration and, in response, Joseph Carens (1987) argues for generally open borders. We also discussed many of the other prominent theorists who have weighed in on these issues, including arguments from Christopher Heath Wellman, Phillip Cole, David Miller, Ryan Pevnick, Mathias Risse, and Michael Blake and we see how a lively contemporary debate continues on these core themes.

      As we have also seen, people defend a range of views under the description of “open borders.” Many of the accounts characterized as “open borders” are really more accurately described as arguing for “fairly open borders” because they permit states to exclude (for instance) known terrorists or to close their borders when a situation of welfare overload has been reached or is foreseeable. We could generally see all the types of arguments we have been considering as positioned along a continuum from “more closed” at one end to “more open” at the other. Even those commonly aligned with an open borders position allow some permissible constraints. And even those who defend reasonably strong rights to close borders argue that there are important constraints on state rights to exclude, such as those presented by requirements concerning how to treat refugees or guest workers, all topics to be studied in greater detail in other chapters of this book.

      1 * Surprisingly little is still known about these victims. For some information see BBC News, “Essex lorry deaths: People found dead were all Vietnamese,” November 1, 2019, available here: https://www.bbc.com/news/uk-england-essex-50268939.

      2 * While it is expected that readers will have a reasonably good understanding of what the idea of self-determination involves, for those who are interested in exploring some of the issues that this idea can present, see David Miller (2020). For instance, some of the core questions that may be puzzling include: Is the idea of self-determination an illusion? Does scope for self-determination genuinely exist in our globally interconnected world? Who are the people who should be self-determining? What if those people don’t agree on how to be self-determining? Why should we value self-determination?

      Конец ознакомительного фрагмента.

      Текст предоставлен ООО «ЛитРес».

      Прочитайте эту книгу целиком,

Скачать книгу