Ethics at the Heart of Higher Education. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Ethics at the Heart of Higher Education - Группа авторов страница 3

Ethics at the Heart of Higher Education - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

the president governs by Twitter. Yet the ethical dilemmas are no less complex than the subject matter; cyber security, prison reform, labor rights, abortion, artificial intelligence, or gun laws are common table topics over lunch. Struggling through that complexity is central to understanding its implications for our culture. As scholar D. Stephen Long so eloquently writes in his chapter, “It is insufficient to inform students that they already have an ethical formation. It must be subject to examination.”

      This book also provides a much-needed overview of the field of Christian ethics, including the Social Gospel movement, Christian realism, Catholic social teaching, the proper role of the state in social and economic life, subsidiarity, religious liberty, human rights, the Christian right, and liberation theology. This grounding demonstrates the depth and complexity of Christian ethics and concludes that the rightful place for such thinking and debate also resides at the university.

      That’s why this book is important.

      1. See Charles Curran, chapter 3.

      2. See Robert Howell, chapter 2.

      3. Brooks, Road to Character, 15.

      1

      Can Ethics Be Taught? Connecting the Classroom to Everyday Life

      D. Stephen Long

      Can we, should we, teach ethics in the modern university? Teaching ethics differs from teaching other disciplines. Few students arrive at the university aware of Organic Chemistry and the importance of Grignard reactions. They most likely have not studied the causes, major dates, or key persons in the French Revolution. The means for teaching and evaluating students in these subjects can be relatively straightforward. Either one has success in the laboratory forming carbon-carbon bonds or one does not. One can give the dates for Robespierre’s life and describe his role in the revolution or one cannot. But what about ethics? Our assumptions about teaching ethics cannot be the same as they are for teaching Organic Chemistry or French History. On the one hand, we assume students already have some sense of ethics before they arrive, which is why we hold them accountable for their behavior from their first day on campus. No one can avoid being disciplined for a violation of an honor code by protesting, “But I have not yet had my ethics course!” We would not hold a student accountable for her ignorance of Grignard reactions or French history prior to receiving instruction in the field, but we do hold students accountable for their actions with or without a course in ethics. On the other hand, we also assume that students should reflect on ethics across the curriculum, and that assumes that ethics needs to and can be taught. How do we make sense of both these assumptions? (1) Students arrive capable of being held accountable for ethical behavior. (2) Students arrive in need of an education in ethics.

      A cursory reading of these assumptions might find them to be contradictory. If students can be held accountable for ethical behavior without an ethics course, then why teach ethics? If students need an education in ethics, then why hold them accountable for ethical failure? This essay explores these two assumptions, noting why they are not contradictory, and why the teaching of ethics should depend and build on the ordinary formation with which students arrive on campus. Teaching ethics in the university will be most successful when it connects with students’ previous histories of doing good and avoiding evil in their everyday life, connects that to the university’s moral history, and points toward the ordinary events that will constitute their future endeavors. It is in these histories that teaching ethics makes best sense.

      If the two assumptions of my opening paragraph are granted—first, we assume students arrive at the university with some understanding of ethical behavior so that we can hold them accountable for their actions even if they never had a course in ethics; second, we assume students should be taught ethics in their curriculum, including courses in ethics across the curriculum—then two possible objections arise based on the possible contradiction present in the assumptions. We could argue that students do not arrive at the university with a sufficient understanding of proper ethical behavior such that we should hold them accountable for their actions. This argument, however, would make the life of the university nearly impossible. Even if we cannot give convincing theoretical reasons why we hold the first assumption, living together in a complex space like the university requires that practically we assume students arrive with at least a tacit awareness of doing good and avoiding evil. We do not need to assume they all share the same ethical convictions, or that every student has the same level of ethical awareness, but the practice of everyday, university life assumes students (along with everyone else associated with the university) have some tacit ethical awareness.

      Universities are composed of adults who have already been formed into ways of seeing the world and acting within it from a diversity of social forms of life. They are also composed

Скачать книгу