Syntax. Andrew Carnie

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Syntax - Andrew Carnie страница 18

Syntax - Andrew Carnie

Скачать книгу

or linguistics background.

      Finally, there are a number of biological arguments in favor of UG. As noted above, language seems to be both human-specific and pervasive across the species. All humans, unless they have some kind of physical impairment, seem to have language as we know it. This points towards it being a genetically endowed instinct. Additionally, research from neurolinguistics seems to point towards certain parts of the brain being linked to specific linguistic functions.

      With very few exceptions, most generative linguists believe that some i-language is innate. What is of controversy is how much is innate and whether the innateness is specific to language, or follows from more general innate cognitive functions. We leave these questions unanswered here.

      You now have enough information to try GPS7 & 8 and CPS10.

      Statistical Probability or UG?

      In looking at the logical problem of language acquisition you might be asking yourself, “Ok, so maybe kids don’t get all the data, but perhaps they get enough to draw conclusions about what is the most likely structure of their grammar?” For example, we might conclude that a child learning English would observe the total absence of any sentences that have that followed by a trace (e.g., 28d), so after hearing some threshold of sentences they conclude that this sentence type is ungrammatical. This is a common objection to the hypothesis of UG. Unfortunately, this hypothesis can’t explain why many sentence types that are extremely rare (to the point that they are probably never heard by children) are still judged as grammatical by the children. For example, English speakers rarely (if ever) produce sentences with seven embeddings (John said that Mary thinks that Susan believes that Matt exclaimed that Marian claimed that Art said that Andrew wondered if Gwen had lost her pen); yet speakers of English routinely agree these are acceptable. The actual speech of adult speakers is riddled with errors (due to all sorts of external factors: memory, slips of the tongue, tiredness, distraction, etc.). However, children do not seem to assume that any of these errors, which they hear frequently, are part of the data that determine their grammars.

       6.5 Explaining Language Variation

      The fact that an inborn system should allow variation won’t be a surprise to any biologist. Think about the color of your eyes. Every sighted person has eyes. Having eyes is clearly an inborn property of being a human (or being a mammal). I doubt that anyone would object to that characterization. Nevertheless we see both widespread variation in eye color, size, and shape among humans, and widespread variation in form and position among various mammalian species. A closer analog to language might be bird song. In 1962, Marler and Tamura observed dialect variation among the songs of white-crowned sparrows. The ability and motivation for these birds to vocalize is widely assumed to be innate, but the particular song they sing is dependent upon the input they hear.

      One way in which languages differ is in terms of the words used in the language. The different words of different languages clearly have to be learned or memorized and are not innate. Other differences between languages must also be acquired. For example the child learning English must determine that its word order is subject-verb-object (SVO), but the child learning Irish determines the order is verb-subject-object (VSO) and the Turkish child figures out subject-object-verb (SOV) order. The explanation for this kind of fact will be explored in more detail in chapter 6. Foreshadowing slightly, we’ll claim there that differences in the grammars of languages can be boiled down to the setting of certain innate parameters (or switches) that select among possible variants. Language variation thus reduces to learning the correct set of words and selecting from a predetermined set of options.

      Oversimplifying slightly, most languages put the elements in a sentence in one of the following word orders:

31) a) Subject Verb Object (SVO) (e.g., English)
b) Subject Object Verb (SOV) (e.g., Turkish)
c) Verb Subject Object (VSO) (e.g., Irish)

      A few languages use

      d) Verb Object Subject (VOS) (e.g., Malagasy)

      No (or almost no13) languages use

      e) Object Subject Verb (OSV)

      f) Object Verb Subject (OVS)

      In his excellent book The Atoms of Language, Mark Baker inventories a set of possible parameters of language variation within the UG hypothesis. This is an excellent and highly accessible treatment of parameters. I strongly recommend this book for further reading on how language variation is consistent with Universal Grammar.

      You now have enough information to try GPS7, GPS8, and CPS 11.

      7. CHOOSING AMONG THEORIES ABOUT SYNTAX

      There is one last preliminary we have to touch on before actually doing some real syntax. In this book we are going to posit many hypotheses. Some of these we’ll keep, others we’ll revise, and still others we’ll reject. How do we know what is a good hypothesis and what is a bad one? Chomsky (1965) proposed that we can evaluate how good theories of syntax are using what are called the levels of adequacy. Chomsky claimed that there are three stages that a grammar (the collection of descriptive rules that constitute your theory) can attain in terms of scientific adequacy.

      If your theory only accounts for the data in a corpus (say a series of printed texts) and nothing more, it is said to be an observationally adequate grammar. Needless to say, this isn’t much use if we are trying to account for the cognition of an i-language. As we discussed above, it doesn’t tell us the whole picture. We also need to know what kinds of sentences are unacceptable, or ill-formed. A theory that accounts for both corpora and native speaker judgments about well-formedness is called a descriptively

Скачать книгу