What is Philosophy of Mind?. Tom McClelland

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу What is Philosophy of Mind? - Tom McClelland страница 6

What is Philosophy of Mind? - Tom McClelland

Скачать книгу

things that turn thought into action – they are the mental states that make things happen. Some hold that this concept of volitions overcomplicates matters. They argue that intentions can cause actions and that there’s no need for a third kind of mental state mediating between the two. For our purposes, we can remain neutral on whether we really have volitions.

      The states we’ve considered have all been conscious mental states – states of which Mindy is aware. But there are good reasons for thinking that our conscious mental life is just the tip of the iceberg, and that below the surface there are countless unconscious mental states. Some unconscious mental states can easily be brought into consciousness. You have the unconscious belief that Paris is the capital of France, but now that I’ve raised the topic of France’s capital, that belief will have become conscious. Other unconscious mental states are much harder to retrieve. You might have an unconscious desire to murder your neighbour that only becomes conscious after months of psychotherapy. There might even be mental states that can never enter our consciousness. Your visual experience is the product of many stages of sensory processing and what goes on in the early stages of this process could well be inaccessible to us.

      Moving on to perception, psychological research has revealed that some perceptual states occur unconsciously. In subliminal perception, your mind registers a stimulus without you being aware of it. Let’s say that the big screen at the football ground quickly flashes an advert for Jaffa Cakes. Mindy could perceive this advert, without even consciously experiencing it. Later on, she might even find herself with an inexplicable craving for Jaffa Cakes! The sensation of pain is an interesting case. It’s tempting to say that you can’t be in pain without that pain being conscious. But what if Mindy were to say, ‘I didn’t notice the pain in my ankle’? Should we conclude that Mindy had an unconscious pain or that the pain only started when Mindy started to have a conscious experience of pain? To answer this, we’d need to refine our understanding of what it is to be in pain and, indeed, our understanding of what it is for a mental state to be conscious.

      What about volitions? On the one hand, you could argue that volitions have to be conscious. It’s not clear how something could be an act of will if it’s unconscious. On the other hand, there are lots of actions we perform without any conscious volition. When absentmindedly driving a familiar road, for example, perhaps each change of gear is the result of an unconscious volition. Again, it’s an open question.

      The foregoing demonstrates the sheer diversity of what happens in the mind. Pains are as different to beliefs as beliefs are to perceptions. We bundle these diverse phenomena under the heading of ‘mental’, but what is it that makes a state mental? To say that Mindy has a certain ‘state’ is just to say that Mindy has some property at a particular time. And there are countless non-mental properties that Mindy has, such as having a body temperature of 37.1° Celsius. But why don’t they qualify as mental?

      Consider the table on the following page. This looks like an intuitive way of organizing Mindy’s states. Although states like Mindy’s muscle fatigue can cause mental states like the feeling of achy muscles, it remains clear that muscle fatigue itself is non-mental. So what determines whether a state goes in the first column or the second? We can ask the same question about the processes Mindy is undergoing. A process is a sequence of states that unfolds over time. For instance, Mindy is in the process of reasoning about where to aim her shot and in the process of digesting her lunch. But what makes the former process mental and the latter nonmental? To answer this, we need to find some defining feature of mentality – a feature possessed by everything in the mental column but nothing in the non-mental column. This elusive feature is known as the mark of the mental.

MENTAL NON-MENTAL
Perceiving the football Having a temperature of 37.1° Celsius
Feeling an ache in her muscles Having a heart rate of 125 beats per minute
Feeling excited Having a blood pressure of 100/70
Believing that the goalkeeper will go left Having muscle fatigue
Desiring that she will score Being well hydrated
Remembering that the goalkeeper went left before Being 6ft tall
Having an intention to kick the ball Being in good physical health

      A more promising proposal is that the mark of the mental is intentionality. The word ‘intentionality’ sounds like it should have something to do with a person’s intentions, but this appearance is misleading. The word is derived from medieval Latin, and to have intentionality is to be about something. Mindy’s perceptual experience, for example, is a perception of the football. So although her perceptual state is something in her mind, that state

Скачать книгу