Gerrymandering. Stephen K. Medvic

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Gerrymandering - Stephen K. Medvic страница 8

Gerrymandering - Stephen K. Medvic

Скачать книгу

than unelected redistricting commissions or judges, who don’t have to answer to anyone for their work. However, those who take the civic redistricting position believe both that elected officials are not as accountable for the maps they draw as we might think and that redistricting commissions can be designed to ensure accountability.

      Imagine what would be required of voters if they were to hold accountable the elected officials drawing maps. A voter would have to be aware of the range of potential maps being considered during the redistricting process and would have to develop a preference for one of the maps (per legislative chamber). Not many voters are apt to gather this information, or even have access to it, and few would come to a judgment on it. If, by some chance, most voters did identify their preferred maps, they could only then punish those responsible for supporting district lines they object to after the maps had been drawn. Thus, even if they were to defeat the offending mapmakers at the next election, the maps those officials drew would be in use for the rest of the decade. (Some states do allow mid-decade redistricting, though in practice this rarely happens and its legality in most of those states is ambiguous at this point.38) Furthermore, the whole point of gerrymandering is to shield one party, or a group of incumbents, from serious electoral threat. How likely is it, then, that elected officials in newly gerrymandered districts are going to be vulnerable in the next election? To the extent that elected officials are invulnerable, there is no real mechanism for accountability.

      We’ll discuss redistricting commissions in detail later in the book. For now, it should simply be noted that there are ways to design independent redistricting commissions so that they are accountable to the citizenry. Indeed, there are ways to design these commissions to allow the public at least some role in the process.39 Accountability can be preserved even if district lines aren’t drawn by elected officials.

      Of course, the redistricting process is not part of constitutional politics either. To be sure, there is a debate over whether partisan gerrymandering is permitted by the Constitution (with most of those in the civic redistricting camp believing it is not, for reasons that will be discussed elsewhere in this book). Those engaged in that debate are, no doubt, involved in constitutional politics. But the redistricting process itself isn’t part of any attempt to alter our understanding of our most foundational document.40 Redistricting, then, occurs – or should occur – within a unique space in American politics. Without reaching the lofty arena of constitutional politics, it ought to nonetheless remain above normal politics.

      In the end, these competing perspectives on the nature of redistricting differ not in terms of how democratic they are but in terms of the way they conceive of democracy. One takes the view that democracy is conflictual and is shot through with politics. This view of democracy is like the American humorist Finley Peter Dunne’s view of politics – it “ain’t beanbag.”41 A free society allows individuals, typically acting in groups, to pursue their own self-interest. This makes democracy a battle between groups of people over the future direction of the country. Given the stakes, we should expect those groups to play hardball and any legal means to achieve one’s ends are permitted.

      Another important consideration in the gerrymandering debate is the nature of representation. Ultimately, a representative democracy must translate the desires of the public into policy. Exactly how that is to be done isn’t obvious.

      The theoretical literature on representation is vast and it is beyond the scope of this chapter to even begin to summarize it.42 For our purposes, representation will refer to the relationship between elected officials and their constituents in which elected officials act on behalf of their constituents in matters of governing. Though representation is always descriptive to some extent (i.e., reflecting demographic characteristics like race, religion, and gender), most of the current discussion about representation in the context of redistricting concerns substantive representation, or the representation of constituents’ policy preferences and ideological perspectives.43 The assumption is that constituents’ preferences ought to be reflected in the voting records of their representatives. If, for example, most constituents in a given area prefer conservative policies, their representatives should support conservative policies.

      From another perspective, the creation of safe districts amounts to rigging the system. A common refrain from this side of the debate is that when gerrymandering is allowed to occur, politicians are picking their voters before voters can pick their politicians. From this point of view, then, the goal is competitive elections. District lines should be drawn in such a way as to maximize competition in as many districts as possible.46 Of course, given that only one representative will be elected per district, a competitive district in which preferences are split roughly 50-50 will mean that about half the constituency will always be unhappy with its representation. Be that as it may, competitive elections are thought to be more effective in holding incumbents accountable, giving voters a meaningful choice over their representation, and generating more excitement and, consequently, more participation than uncompetitive elections. These effects, it is argued, are vital for a healthy democracy.

      There are those who would argue that the question of whether an institution, like Congress, is representative in a collective sense is largely irrelevant. The American system of government, they argue, is not designed to achieve collective representation at least in majoritarian terms. Features like the separation of powers, bicameralism, and federalism mean that it is purposefully difficult to translate majority preferences into policy. Representation in institutions like the US Senate and the presidency (via the Electoral College) is geographically

Скачать книгу