Devolution and Autonomy in Education. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Devolution and Autonomy in Education - Группа авторов страница 6

Devolution and Autonomy in Education - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

both foundational and applied research (International Council for Science 2004). Its object of study is specified, and it specifically concerns mathematics; however nothing refers to school or teaching, which represent institutional and historical choices concerning only part of the diffusion of mathematical knowledge or the study of it. In the continuation of the previous quotation, Brousseau, when he specifies the “restricted meaning”, indicates a “teaching” institution but assigns to it a meaning that is not necessarily that conferred on it by contemporary usage (employee in national education).

      The didactics of mathematics deals (in a restricted sense) with the conditions where an institution considered a “teaching” institution attempts (mandated if necessary by another institution) to modify the knowledge of another “taught” institution when the latter is not able to do so autonomously and does not necessarily feel the need to do so. A didactic project is a social project to enable a subject or an institution to appropriate knowledge that has been or is in the process of being created. Teaching includes all the actions that seek to achieve this didactic project (Brousseau 2003, p. 2).

      In this quotation, a very important point that will be developed is that the “taught institution” does not necessarily feel the need to change its knowledge and is not able to do so autonomously. As I am only interested here in one teaching institution, the school, I will speak of students and teachers.

      The concept of devolution

      In his glossary, Guy Brousseau considers devolution a process that he defines as follows:

      He completes this definition in the article “le paradoxe de la dévolution”:

      In the following section, I will come back to some elements of these glossary articles, and first, I will attempt to characterize the terms “institutional knowledge” and “situational knowledge”, which Brousseau uses deliberately in the above articles.

      Institutional knowledge and situational knowledge: a fundamental distinction

      The distinction between institutional knowledge and situational knowledge exists in the philosophical field, in which it seems to have different delimitations depending on the authors, if we refer to a blog in which the subject appears (Juignet 2016):

      It is, however, interesting to distinguish the active process of production, which we shall call “situational knowledge” from its result, which we shall call “institutional knowledge” or “acquired knowledge”. It is a question of applying the difference between action and its result, which is tantamount to saying that the act of putting knowledge into action produces knowledge.

      Situational knowledge implies an active relationship with the world that aims to represent and explain it. This activity generally combines action and reflection. There are various types of knowledge that are more or less effective, reliable and realistic.

      Institutional knowledge is the corpus of accepted and transmitted notions, the organized set of information in a given field. Part of the institutional knowledge represents the world in a certain way and can be used for practical purposes. It only needs to be learned and is accumulated over generations, thus forming culture.

      The distinction that is made within the framework of situation theory is close to this one, although some important points are specified.

      In a situation, a subject is interacting with an milieu and is seeking to realize an issue, and to do so focuses on situational knowledge, which represents a balance between the subject and the milieu (Balacheff and Margolinas 2005; Margolinas 2014). In this sense, situational knowledge is not “in the subject” and not “in the milieu” either, it exists in the interaction between the two. In situations of action (Brousseau 1981), situational knowledge is a priori implicit and often not explainable. The different types of mathematical situations described by Brousseau aim to transform this situational knowledge by modifying the necessities of the situation, whether a formulation situation (formulation becomes necessary) or a validation situation (proof becomes necessary).

Скачать книгу