The Perspective of Love. R. J. Snell

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Perspective of Love - R. J. Snell страница 13

Автор:
Серия:
Издательство:
The Perspective of Love - R. J. Snell

Скачать книгу

about theory in its classical structure, namely its anticipation of invariance, necessity, and universality. Recall that in pursuing an heuristic ideal, the unknown x anticipates answers of a certain kind.91 Common sense thinks it understands when it can point, manipulate successfully, and use common language well. But physics doesn’t think this, judging instead that “laws are reached by eliminating the relations of things to the senses of observers and by arriving at relations between the things . . . then there exists . . . the affirmation that principles and laws are the same for all observers because they lie simply and completely outside the range of observational activities.”92 In other words, theory, at least in its classical form, expects to find intelligibility as universal, invariant, and necessary, as that which cannot be otherwise than it is. It expects to find laws, as in classical laws of physics. The contingent is not fully intelligible, since we possess properly scientific knowledge, “as opposed to knowing it in the accidental way in which the sophist knows, when we think that we know the cause on which the fact depends, as the cause of that fact and of no other, and, further, that the fact could not be other than it is. . . . the proper object of unqualified scientific knowledge is something which cannot be other than it is.”93 Further, properly scientific demonstration “must rest on necessary basic truths; for the object of scientific knowledge cannot be other than it is,” and consequently, the first premises must be basic, or self-evident, and the reasoning from them logically valid deductions, which would be necessarily true.94

      Theory and the Real

      Although articulated differently, both Plato and Aristotle consider the formal necessity grasped in theory to be real and objectively knowable, and thus metaphysics became the master science. In common sense, the real was envisioned as bodies, as the “already out there now real,” or presence, what could be seen or touched, because common sense begins with an anticipation of what exists in relation to me and my sensation. Since concern is for that which exists in relation to me, I expect that what exists is that which exists over and against me, and being is modeled after bodies. With theory, being is whatever is intended as meaningful, and only the invariant and necessary is fully meaningful:

      Metaphysics is a science, and thus will follow the rules of the other sciences, just having greater extension and thus abstraction, but metaphysics follows entirely the rules implicit in theory’s anticipation of meaning.

      Theory as Law

      Note the anticipation for data to “conform to some law.” The heuristic shapes what we anticipate, and thus how we interpret what we find, in an interesting pivoting of discovery and anticipation. We anticipate intelligibility under a certain heuristic, thereby discovering such intelligibility in the data given to us. For instance, Theatetus mentions that Theodorus began to teach about squares with the assistance of diagrams, namely, that which could be viewed and imagined, so to arrive at the formula after the intelligible principle was discovered through the use of the data supplied by the diagrams. But many people could look at the diagrams and find no intelligibility; only those anticipating finding something, only those looking for something, some unknown x of a certain type find x. Once found, the formula governs the anticipation of how additional instances will be understood, even before those instances are diagramed. So our anticipation allows for discovery which provides the basis for ongoing anticipation.

Скачать книгу