Judgments of Beauty in Theory Evaluation. Devon Brickhouse-Bryson

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Judgments of Beauty in Theory Evaluation - Devon Brickhouse-Bryson страница 9

Серия:
Издательство:
Judgments of Beauty in Theory Evaluation - Devon Brickhouse-Bryson

Скачать книгу

in the world’s great art museums.11 The artworks that people overwhelmingly regard as beautiful (perhaps from Monet or Van Gogh) are equally beautiful (or equally ugly) as all other artworks, even the most amateurish or clumsy. If relativism about beauty is true, then as long as someone earnestly claims that an artwork is beautiful, then it ipso facto is beautiful. And vice versa: as long as someone earnestly claims that an artwork is ugly, then it ipso facto is ugly. This is absurd. The history of art—which traces the arc of great and beautiful artworks and the masters of creating such beauty—would be utterly idle and misguided. The institutions dedicated to promoting and preserving great and beautiful art—museums, concert halls, architectural preservation societies, UNESCO, and so on—would be utterly idle and misguided. Our histories of art and institutions of art are by no means perfect: they make omissions, have biases, can be drawn to fame over quality, and so on. (Note that even saying that histories and institutions of art could make mistakes about beauty assumes non-relativism about beauty.) But to admit that these are not perfect is of course not to say that they have not captured some truth about the beauty of artworks. It is an absurd implication of relativism about beauty that there are no genuinely beautiful artworks.

      Thinking about the histories of art and the institutions of art in this context points to yet another absurd implication of relativism about beauty: that there is no expertise about beauty. The projects of art history, of art institutions, of art criticism, of art appreciation are all predicated on the premise that some artworks are genuinely beautiful and worthy of admiration. One can be trained to appreciate these beautiful artworks by training in technique, by repeated exposure, by expert guidance, and by learning some of the history of art and beauty. All of this is idle and meaningless if relativism about beauty is true. If an amateur earnestly claimed that their artwork was the most beautiful in all history, then that claim would be utterly on a par with the museum curator’s judgment that another artwork was more beautiful. If a stubborn student earnestly claimed that an artwork was not beautiful, then that claim would be utterly on a par with the art appreciation professor’s judgment that it was beautiful. Although experts about beautiful artwork can make mistakes (like any expert), this does not undermine the common sense that it is possible to be an expert critic of beauty. Relativism about beauty throws such expertise to the wind, which is an absurd implication.

      Note that all these absurd implications of relativism about beauty relate to commonsense features of our judgments of beauty and the ordinary ways we interact with beauty. We make, revise, and improve our judgments of beauty; we engage in critical disputes about the beauty of artworks; we travel the world to see especially beautiful buildings, artworks, and landscapes; we listen to the expertise of art critics. None of this would be sensible if relativism about beauty were true and that painful revision to our considered judgments about beauty is enough to warrant the denial of relativism about beauty. But there is one more absurd implication for relativism about beauty related to our ordinary experience of beauty. Above I examined several arguments for relativism about beauty that were based on disagreement about beauty. I responded that those arguments, even granting their premises about disagreement about beauty, do not entail relativism about beauty. But here is another problem with relativism and disagreement about beauty: there is significant agreement about judgments of beauty as well, even across time and culture. There is widespread, persistent agreement that the Taj Mahal, Yosemite Valley, Hokusai’s The Great Wave off Kanagawa, and Beethoven’s 9th Symphony are all very beautiful. There are countless other buildings, natural landscapes, paintings, pieces of music, and so on that we could list that would command widespread agreement on their beauty. There is, of course, some disagreement about beauty: even on these paradigm cases, there will be a few stubborn or strange detractors. And there are certainly cases that are less clear: we are far less certain about whether many cases of modern art are beautiful (of course, many cases of modern art are purposefully not supposed to be beautiful).12 If relativism about beauty were true, then there should not be such patterns of agreement. If relativism about beauty were true, then our judgments of beauty should whimsically dart in every direction: a judgment of beauty would be true in virtue of being claimed, so true claims about beauty should be utterly haphazard. Relativism about beauty cannot explain the significant agreement about beauty that we experience and a theory’s running roughshod over that body of data is enough to deny that theory.

      All of these absurd implications of relativism about beauty can be tied together by noting that relativism about beauty reduces beauty to an empty concept. If relativism about beauty is true, then there is really no truth about beauty at all. According to relativism, all claims about beauty are equally true, equally false, depending on whether they are claimed or denied. But this is better understood as asserting that claims of beauty are neither true nor false at all. If claims about beauty were properly true and false at the same time and the same respect, then straightforward contradictions are generated and relativism falsifies itself. Thus, relativism should understand claims of beauty as strictly speaking neither true nor false. Relativism must maintain, on pain of contradiction, that all claims about beauty—everyone’s individual claims, claims about improvement, claims about great artworks, claims about art expertise, patterns of agreement about beauty—are strictly speaking neither true nor false. This means that there are no truth conditions that govern the concept of beauty at all, which makes it an utterly empty concept.13 Thus, relativism about beauty—in the myriad ways I’ve argued above—destroys the concept of beauty in a way that runs utterly roughshod over our considered judgments of beauty. The most fundamental of these considered judgments is merely the considered judgment that beauty is a real and important concept. This considered judgment underpins our enjoyment of beauty, our attention to beauty-related greatness and expertise, our patterns of agreement about beauty, and our critical discussion of beauty when faced with disagreement. Relativism about beauty strikes at this most fundamental of considered judgments of beauty—that it is real—and so relativism should be rejected. Relativism’s violence to our considered judgments about beauty is enough reason to justify belief in the denial of relativism.

      Arguments against Relativism from an Analogy to Moral Relativism

      These arguments against relativism about beauty should sound familiar. They are closely analogous with arguments against relativism about morality. Although relativism about morality does not enjoy as widespread endorsement as relativism about beauty, anyone who has spent some time teaching ethics knows that relativism about morality is often (uncritically) endorsed. It is often the first task of teaching ethics to uproot a naïve relativism about morality; the arguments that are used against relativism about morality track the arguments against relativism about beauty given above. Disagreement (including intractable or even necessarily intractable) about morality is commonly cited as reason to believe in relativism about morality.14 But the counter to this argument is likewise to point out that disagreement does not entail relativism, given that disagreement is an epistemic phenomenon and that relativism is about the truth status of moral claims. If disagreement about morality does not license moral relativism, then neither does disagreement about beauty license relativism about beauty.

      The analogy continues: if driving a wedge between disagreement and relativism is not enough to undermine relativism about morality, then the argument against relativism usually proceeds to point out the many ways in which relativism about morality runs roughshod over our moral considered judgments. Relativism about morality means that moral claims are true merely in virtue of being claimed. This has several implications, given that people can claim all kinds of things about morality: (1) that people cannot be wrong in their earnest claims about morality, (2) that they cannot improve their moral beliefs (since all moral beliefs are equally true/false), (3) that no action is any more or less moral than any other action (since someone could believe that any action is moral), (4) that there is no such thing as moral expertise,15 and (5) that patterns of agreement about morality are mere coincidence. These are all profoundly counterintuitive implications; together they make morality an utterly empty concept. The violence that relativism about morality does to our considered judgments about morality is enough reason to reject relativism about morality. Or, at least, this is often the kind of argument that is used to reject relativism about morality. If this kind of argument is successful, then my arguments against

Скачать книгу