Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience. P. M. S. Hacker

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience - P. M. S. Hacker страница 41

Philosophical Foundations of Neuroscience - P. M. S. Hacker

Скачать книгу

within the modules and between the modules. A key component of the hypothesis is that the unity of conscious experience is provided by the self-conscious mind and not by the neuronal machinery of the liaison areas of the cerebral cortex. Hitherto it has been impossible to develop any neurophysiological theory that explains how a diversity of brain events comes to be synthesized so that there is a unified conscious experience … My general hypothesis regards the neuronal machinery as a multiplex of radiating and receiving structures ( modules). The experienced unity comes, not from a neurophysiological synthesis, but from the proposed integrating character of the self-conscious mind. I conjecture that in the first place the raison d’être of the self-conscious mind is to give this unity of the self in all its conscious experiences and actions.(HM 227f.)

      How does the mind engage in this activity of synthesis (or ‘binding’)? Eccles suggested that the mind

      plays through the whole liaison brain in a selective and unifying manner. The analogy is provided by a searchlight. Perhaps a better analogy would be some multiple scanning and probing device that reads out from and selects from the immense and diverse patterns of activity in the cerebral cortex and integrates these selected components, so organizing them into the unity of conscious experience … Thus I conjecture that the self-conscious mind is scanning the modular activities in the liaison areas of the cerebral cortex … From moment to moment it is selecting modules according to its interests, the phenomena of attention, and is itself integrating from all this diversity to give the unified conscious experience.(HM 229)

      Four flaws in Eccles’s conception

       (1) The phenomena resultant upon hemispherectomy were misdescribed

       (2) The ‘self-conscious mind’ is not an entity of any kind

      Second, the so-called self-conscious mind is not an entity of any kind, but a capacity of human beings who have mastered a reflexive language. They can therefore ascribe experiences to themselves and reflect on the experiences thus ascribed (see §14.6). But the ‘self-conscious mind’ is not the sort of thing that can intelligibly be said to be ‘in contact with’ the brain ( let alone with something denominated ‘the liaison brain’).

       (3) Incoherence in Eccles’s hypothesis

      Third, Eccles’s main hypothesis is unintelligible. If the self-conscious mind were, per impossibile, ‘actively engaged in reading out’ from areas in the dominant hemisphere and ‘selecting from these modules according to attention’, then the self-conscious mind would have to perceive or be aware of the neural modules in question (otherwise how could it ‘read them out’?), and know which ones to select for its purpose (otherwise the wrong ones might constantly be selected). Or, to put matters more lucidly, for any of this story to make sense, human beings would have to be aware of the neural structures and operations in question, and, from moment to moment, decide which ones directly to activate, and, of course, have the capacity to do so. But we possess no such knowledge and no such capacity.

      (4) The very notion of the self-conscious mind presupposes the unity of experience

      Finally, it is confused to suppose that the raison d’être of the ‘self-conscious mind’ is to engender the unity of the self and, as our contemporaries would put it, ‘solve the binding problem’. For any talk of a person or of a human being as having a mind already presupposes the unity of experience and cannot be invoked to explain it.

      Eccles’s errors cannot be rectified by substituting the brain for his conception of the ‘self-conscious mind’

      2.4 Wilder Penfield and the ‘Highest Brain Mechanism’

      Penfield’s training

      Wilder Penfield (1891–1976) was born in Spokane, Washington. After graduating from Princeton in 1913, he won a Rhodes Scholarship to Oxford and entered the School of Physiology there to begin his medical studies under the inspiring influence of Sherrington. He followed Sherrington’s interest in histology and, in particular, in neurocytology. After obtaining his BA in physiology at Oxford, he went to the Johns Hopkins Medical School, where he finished his medical degree in 1918. His first research concerned changes in the Golgi apparatus of neurons after axonal section. In 1924 he began to study the healing processes of surgical wounds in the brain. On Sherrington’s advice, he spent some time in Madrid working with Pio del Rio-Hortega, learning to use the histological methods of his brilliant teacher Ramón y Cajal. To this end, surgical specimens of brain scars were collected from patients who had been operated on for post-traumatic epilepsy.

      Penfield’s achievement

      Penfield

Скачать книгу