Environmental Ethics. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Environmental Ethics - Группа авторов страница 20

Environmental Ethics - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

of Embeddedness–A.53

      3 All humans will value as “prudentially good” that which allows them personally to act–F.

      4 All humans, personally, will value as “prudentially good” the acquisition of as many goods from the Table of Embeddedness as possible (in hierarchical order)—1−3.

      5 Respecting the general grounds of action, all humans are alike—F.

      6 Respecting the general grounds of human action, logically there can be no idiosyncratic preference—5.

      7 Whatever attaches as an essential Natural condition of a species viewed contextually from the various community worldview imperatives (shared human, extended human, eco, and extended eco) is proper to that Natural species condition—F.

      8 To be “mutually life-affirming in an environmental perspective” is a fundamental positive normative environmental value—A.54

      9 Whatever is proper to a Natural species condition is morally good if the summation of all and every Natural species conditions (i.e., general, generic conditions) are mutually life-affirming in an environmental perspective—5−8.

      10 The prudential values set out in premise #4 (for individuals) can be generally life-affirming in an environmental perspective—9.

      11 Prudential values for particular individuals in an environmental context become general moral values when they attach to generic Natural species conditions—9, 10.

      12 The prudential values set out in premise #4 are morally good and incur positive moral duties on all (capable of voluntary action) to facilitate outcomes that are life-affirming in an environmental perspective—4, 9, 11.

      Argument Two: The Moral Perspective of Human Nature Within the Environmental Perspective

      Argument Two, though it begins with prudential values (seen from the perspective of individual natures), transcends to the ethical when the understanding of the relationship between humans and their fundamental definition is generalized within the environmental context. This is because there is no longer an agent acting for themself only. Rather, the logical substitution instance is a generically described individual and, as such, could be understood as applicable to any substitution instance for the variable that has undergone universal generalization.

      1 There is a priority in the process of making that puts the maker above the output of the maker: things made—A.

      2 The status of priority in the process of making means that the operation of and the interests in the maker always trump the operation of and the interests in the things made—A.

      3 Nature’s relation to Humans is as maker to output made—F.

      4 The operation of and the interests in Nature’s systemic operation always trumps the operation of and the interests of Human’s own making—1−3.

      5 The operation of and the interests in Human artifacts (technology) are always subservient to the ultimate interests of Humans—1, 4.

      6 The operation of and interests in Human artifacts (technology) are always subservient to the operation of and interests in Nature’s systemic operation—4, 5.

      Argument Three: The Priority of the Maker Over the Maker’s Output

      Argument Three has some interesting corollaries. Among these are that if we rank the priority normatively, from the vantage point of the thing made, the maker is (in an important sense) normatively good. This would make Nature (from the point of view of Humans and all other living things) good. In turn, if Nature is good and if technology created by Humans harms the operation of Nature, then that human technology is bad and ought not be adopted. This gradation of the evil is a function of how much harm Nature incurs.

      What we are left with in this second section of the chapter is a moral commitment to care for Nature. This moral commitment is based upon what Nature is (a series of concentric and overlapping human and Natural communities that are symbiotic). As humans, the study of Nature creates the value/duty relationship that outlines the ground of general moral duty from the human side. Then, this general ground becomes more practical when it is specified that there is a moral prohibition not to interfere in a harmful way with our human makings because Nature stands in relation to all of us as “maker.” As such, Nature’s makings (which includes us) requires the respect owed to a maker not to have its own artifacts come back to harm it. This second principle grounds our practical duties to Nature and acts as a firm moral limitation on human technology.

      Notes

      1 

Скачать книгу