Agape and Hesed-Ahava. David L. Goicoechea

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Agape and Hesed-Ahava - David L. Goicoechea страница 25

Agape and Hesed-Ahava - David L. Goicoechea Postmodern Ethics

Скачать книгу

attitude that is given me by grace and which I then will.

      This attitude that I can have toward nature, humans,

      and spiritual beings is contrasted with the I-it attitude

      in that the I-thou is exclusive, direct, present, and

      mutual while the I-it does not relate to the other as unique

      and mediates the relation with knowledge and relates to it

      in the past and the it does not relate mutually to me.

      Buber shows how it is the exalted melancholy of our fate

      that every thou in our world must become an it, but

      with grace and will they can once again become our thou.

      Also, in every I-thou relation we do meet the eternal thou.

      On pages 68 and 69 of Totality and Infinity Levinas says that he

      does not have the ridiculous pretension of “correcting” Buber, but

      he is critical of the mutuality of the I-Thou relation and thereby

      thinks of our responsibility called forth by the face of the other as

      a “me voici” relation rather than an “I-Thou” relation in order

      to give the other that height of being more important than myself.

      For Levinas the I is the subject of my totality that is nourished

      by enjoyment and will kill for a crust of bread in preferring self.

      The me of the “me voici,” the “here is me” at your service, is

      the me of the accusative, genitive, dative, ablative, vocative,

      responsible self who will give the bread out of my mouth to the other

      so that it is given to me to give by the call of the other who is

      to be served by me with a duty that is mine before the other I.

      Levinas builds upon the notion of love as responsibility of an I

      for a thou by seeing love as coming from the lowly humble me

      who can serve the noble other as the I who makes demands on me.

      II,1.5 And a Transcendence beyond Plato’s Divine Madness

      Plato’s philosophy explains this world of Heraclitean physical

      becoming in terms of the Parmenidean metaphysical realm of Being.

      This realm of Being is central to Heidegger’s ontology and is not

      all that helpful when it comes to formulating a sensitive ethics.

      But Levinas sees in Plato’s metaphysics a Good beyond Being

      that the Platonic philosophy of love in both The Symposium

      and in The Phaedrus gets in touch with as the Beautiful Good.

      On page 43 of Totality and Infinity, Levinas writes:

      Western philosophy has most often been an ontology:

      a reduction of the other to the same

      by interposition of a middle and neutral term

      that ensures the comprehension of being.

      Just above that on the same page he writes:

      A calling into question of the same

      which cannot occur within the egoist

      spontaneity of the same

      is brought about by the other.

      We name this calling into question

      of my spontaneity

      by the presence of the Other ethics.

      On page 48 Levinas begins to discuss “Transcendence as the Idea

      of Infinity” and he shows how the metaphysics of Plato and

      Descartes discovers a divine infinity that is transcendent.

      To think the infinite, the transcendent, is not to think an object.

      On page 49 he writes:

      The “intentionality” of transcendence

      is unique in its kind;

      the difference between objectivity and transcendence

      will serve as a general guideline

      for all the analyses of this work.

      He then discusses the divine madness of Plato’s sublimated eros.

      II,1.6 And an Infinity beyond Descartes’ Infinite

      Levinas treats Plato and Descartes together as he shows how

      they each in different ways had a transcendent infinity

      in their metaphysics and this was felt in Plato’s Phaedrus.

      On page 49 Levinas writes:

      Against a thought that proceeds from him

      who “has his own head to himself,”

      he affirms the value of the delirium

      that comes from God, “winged thought.”

      This enthusiasm and divine madness is thought in its highest

      sense and is a kind of ecstatic possession by the divine Other.

      Plato discovered something akin to Levinas’s infinity that calls

      me and teaches me of the other when I behold the face of the other.

      Levinas shows how Plato and Descartes are not thinking of

      an object but are in touch with the transcendent, the other.

      However, the transcendence that is the point of Levinas’s book

      does not empower the I by sublimating the power of vulgar passion

      to become the energy of noble passion and its new creativity.

      Rather, the face of the other, as Levinas writes on page 50,

       lets the desire proper to the gaze

      turn

Скачать книгу