Adam Smith. Craig Smith
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу Adam Smith - Craig Smith страница 12
Wonder, Surprise, and Admiration
At the heart of his argument is the idea that we are prompted to science not by reason, but by our emotions. Smith believed that we do not originally pursue science for the utilitarian reasons that Francis Bacon had suggested. Instead our scientific method is an extension of an emotionally driven need to understand the world. Science has its origins in our emotions; more specifically it arises from three particular emotions: ‘Wonder, Surprise, and Admiration’.4 When we come across something that we have never encountered before, we try to situate it in relation to our past experience, and when we cannot do this, it makes us uneasy.
Smith thought that this was precisely because our knowledge of the world comes in the form of habitual generalizations drawn from experience. Our understanding of things is a pattern of connections that exist in the imagination and which help to orientate us. The ‘natural career of the imagination’5 flows smoothly and allows us to make sense of the world until it comes across something that does not fit with our established mental patterns. The emotion of wonder is produced when we come across something we have never encountered before; we are surprised by the new or by the familiar appearing in an unexpected context; and we admire an explanation that is able to fit the wondrous and surprising into a coherent account of nature. Smith’s point here is that our pursuit of understanding of the world comes from a natural curiosity that is driven by our emotions.
Surprises are unsettling, they upset the smooth operation of our minds, and this uneasiness, this anxiety, is what drives us to science. Smith thinks that our first inclination is to try to account for a surprising event by fitting it into our established patterns of knowledge. If we can do this, our uneasiness dissipates. Indeed we become content and admire the way in which we have been able to place the phenomenon within a system of understanding. Smith regards this experience as both emotional (anxiety dissipating) and aesthetic (in the sense that we admire the beauty of the systematic explanation). Once someone has provided us with an explanation, we are no longer puzzled. Like someone who has seen behind the stage curtain, the special effects of the opera no longer strike us with awe – instead we admire them for the manner in which they are systematically arranged to produce the desired result. However, if we are unable to do this, we remain anxious to make sense of the phenomenon.
It is at this point that we develop more sophisticated systems of understanding. Here Smith makes a startling claim: that the first attempts to respond to the wondrous were religious. Smith provides us with an account of the development of polytheistic religion as a natural attempt to make sense of things that do not fit with established experience. Floods, lightning, famine, are made explicable by seeing them as the deliberate actions of a deity.6 The anger of a superhuman entity might seem an odd source of consolation, but it is better than something that is totally inexplicable. The psychologically unsettling impact of the inexplicable is far worse than that which is supernaturally explicable. This provides a degree of calmness to the mind as we now have some sort of explanation. Such superstitions arise from exactly the same emotional needs as science. The difference for Smith is that science becomes more successful at banishing unease than superstitious religions.
It’s important to understand why science comes to displace superstition and how Smith thought that this had happened in particular societies. First of all, he thought that certain social conditions had to be in place before a scientific method could be developed. Science is only possible when ‘order and security’7 have been secured and people have been freed from absolute want. It is only when we develop some leisure time to pursue our curiosity that we are able to recognize the order that exists in nature and to develop a conscious system of scientific inquiry to understand it. Poverty and superstition go together because the struggle to secure subsistence occupies all of our attention and leaves us ignorant. Science is also facilitated by the division of labour. A separate class of professional philosophers emerges who set their mind to observing nature and seeking its patterns. As this develops, the branches of knowledge divide and specialists develop.
Once the scientific method arises, it begins to supplant superstition precisely because it is more systematic and coherent in its ability to explain the world. In order to understand Smith’s view here and his entire understanding of the task of philosophy, it’s vital to grasp that he sees the task of religious explanations and science as the same. They try to make sense of the world and to calm the mind by banishing anxiety. The test of all such explanations is that they are able to account for what is experienced. A theory or a system of thinking must be subject to a ‘reality check’. If it fails adequately to lead our minds through the order of nature in a smooth fashion, then it will be supplanted by another account that is able to achieve this.
Philosophy is the ‘science of the connecting principles of nature’.8 Its success depends on its ability to render things ‘familiar to the imagination’.9 Smith sums up his view in the following terms:
Philosophy, by representing the invisible chains which bind together all these disjointed objects, endeavours to introduce order into this chaos of jarring and discordant appearances, to allay this tumult of the imagination, and to restore it, when it surveys the great revolutions of the universe, to that tone of tranquillity and composure, which is both most agreeable in itself, and most suitable to its nature.10
Smith’s account of the development of science is undertaken through an account of the move from one system of thought to another. For Smith, a system is an ‘imaginary machine invented to connect together in the fancy those different movements and effects which are already in reality performed’.11 A system for Smith suggests a coherent body of explanation, a theory that accounts for more than one observed phenomenon. Recognizing that there are regularities in nature is what leads humanity from the belief in a multiplicity of gods acting on their own whims to a monotheistic conception of God acting in accordance with rules of nature. One principle that explains a great many things is better at relieving our ‘anxious curiosity’12 and leading our imagination in a smooth fashion. Once we begin the self-conscious exploration of the world through observation, we begin the attempt to organize our ideas into a single coherent system, making sense of the world by ordering our thoughts and calming our minds.13
Systems
Smith then provides us with an account of the gradual evolution of astronomy as a science. The point of this, as we noted above, is to illustrate the more general point about how we come to understand the world. Smith’s account tells us how one system of astronomy is replaced by another, and it is in the detail of this process that we learn why it is that the scientific method has become such an effective means of satisfying our curiosity. Smith’s account relies upon two basic principles that lead us to prefer one system of thought to another and which provide increasingly intellectually and emotionally satisfactory explanations. The first of these is that if our imagination is to be led smoothly, then there must be as few ‘gaps’14 as possible in a theory. If a theory fails to account for part of the observed phenomenon, then we will notice the gap and the lingering anxiety will remain. The system with the fewest such gaps at any one time is the one most likely to be favoured. New theories arise in response to dissatisfaction at the gaps in existing accounts, and in order to succeed they must not only account for the gap, but also account for all that the preceding theory had explained. A new theory must be ‘more completely coherent’15 than its predecessors.
Smith’s second basic principle is the Newtonian preference for identifying a few simple generalizations that explain a multiplicity of phenomena. Explanatory simplicity – elegance, you might say – not only makes it easier for the mind to follow the theory, but it also avoids the danger of a convoluted account that fails to dispel our anxiety. If the system of ideas necessary to explain a complex phenomenon is as complex as the phenomenon itself, then it will fail to relieve the ‘embarrassment’16 in