Astrobiology. Charles S. Cockell

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Astrobiology - Charles S. Cockell страница 28

Astrobiology - Charles S. Cockell

Скачать книгу

of entities we might consider as “life,” but that they do not provide an unambiguous description of living things.

      Physicist Erwin Schrödinger (1887–1961; Figure 2.11) famously attempted to describe life in his seminal book, What is Life?, published in 1944 following a series of lectures given at Trinity College, Dublin, in 1943. Quite apart from some fascinating predictions about the nature of genetic material (that it was an “aperiodic” crystal – a crystal that lacks long-range order – for which he attempted to estimate the size), he also attempted to get at the nature of life.

Portrait of Erwin Schrödinger.

       Figure 2.11 Erwin Schrödinger. He attempted to understand life from a physical perspective.

      Source: Reproduced with permission of wikicommons.

      Schrödinger recognized that life made “order from disorder,” and, employing the second law of thermodynamics, according to which entropy (a measure of the homogenization of energy) increases as energy is dissipated in atoms or molecules, Schrödinger explained that life evades the decay to thermodynamic equilibrium by maintaining what he termed “negative entropy,” for example by gathering energy. The phrase “negative entropy” is rather unwieldy and counter-intuitive. It should be seen more as a popular statement about his views on life rather than an attempt to define a real physical process. The notion of negative entropy is not limited to life, however. Chemical reactions such as endothermic reactions (reactions that take up energy) are in some sense extracting energy from the surrounding environment to increase order.

      Schrödinger's interpretation tends to give the impression that life is “struggling” against the laws of physics – attempting to maintain order against the ineluctable forces of the Universe that tend to disperse it into disorder. The problem with this view is that it does not explain why life is so successful. If living things are constantly struggling against the laws of physics, why does life seem to have been so tenacious and ubiquitous once it got started on Earth?

      Another related way to view life is to focus less on the organisms themselves and their characteristics as single entities, and more on the process that life is involved with. We can think of life as a process driving the Universe more efficiently toward disorder than non-biological processes.

      As with the individual characteristics of life, however, dissipative processes are not unique to life. The Universe is full of patterns and structures that result from the dissipation of energy. An example is the convective cells in the surface of the Sun (Figure 2.12). These complex structures emerge from convective cells that become spontaneously established within the material at the Sun's surface and represent an efficient way for heat to be dissipated. You can sometimes see similar convective cells in a pan of water or milk boiling on a stove. This emerging complexity results from the dissipation of energy. There is no mysterious physics at work. Similarly, living things are thought to represent exquisite examples of dissipative structures. Although living things are more complex than convective cells, the principles of emergent complexity that result from their dissipative behaviors are nonetheless merely physics at work. The elegance of this idea is that it explains why life is successful. It is not fighting the laws of physics, but is a consequence of these laws.

Image described by caption.

       Figure 2.12 Complex structures can emerge in non-biological dissipative structures, such as these convective cells in the surface of the Sun. Each cell is about 700–1000 km across. We would not describe these dissipative structures as alive.

      An obvious corollary, and implication, of these ideas is that life might be inevitable. Just as convective cells inevitably form in heated fluids and gases as a consequence of physical principles, if living things are merely dissipative structures, then the suggestion is that on any planet with liquid water, organic molecules, and appropriate environmental conditions for the assembly of replicating molecules, physical laws will essentially drive the emergence of life. You might like to discuss and debate this idea with others.

      Thus far, we have seen that it is difficult to define life. An obvious problem seems to be our inability to uniquely list or state the characteristics that sharply separate it from non-life. One answer to the problem of the definition of life is that life is simply a human word, an artificial definition created by us. It is what philosophers would call “a non-natural kind,” as opposed to a “natural kind.”

Stacks of flat gold bars.

       Figure 2.13 Gold can be uniquely defined using physical characteristics such as its melting temperature and atomic mass number. Is life in the same category of object?

      A good example of a “non-natural kind” is a “chair” (Figure 2.14). If we define it as “something we can sit on,” then does that make my coffee table a chair? You might reply that a coffee table is not a chair because it has no vertical back on it. I might then show you a stool and claim that it too can therefore not be a chair and is more like a table. Thus, we launch into an endless circular discussion about what a chair is. The conversation is rather pointless because ultimately a chair is simply what we define it to be. If that includes coffee tables then so be it.

A wooden chair.

       Figure 2.14 Perhaps life is more like a chair? Something whose definition depends more on human categorizations, rather than any fundamental physically derivable difference with other materials.

Скачать книгу