The Philosopher's Toolkit. Julian Baggini

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Philosopher's Toolkit - Julian Baggini страница 20

The Philosopher's Toolkit - Julian  Baggini

Скачать книгу

the premises are false (see 1.4).

      There is a third method of refutation, too – or at least quasi‐refutation. All you have to do is simply show that the conclusion must be false. From this it can be argued that therefore, even if you can’t identify exactly what is wrong with the argument, something must be wrong with it (see 3.25). This last method, however, isn’t strictly speaking a refutation, since one has failed to show what is wrong with the argument, only that it must be wrong. Nevertheless, this understanding that something must be wrong often accomplishes all that’s needed.

      Inadequate justification

      Conceptual problems

      More contentiously, you might also reject an argument by arguing that it utilises a concept inappropriately. This sort of problem is particularly clear in cases where a vague concept is used as if it were precise. For instance, consider the claim that the government is obliged to provide assistance only to those who do not have enough to live on properly. But given that there can be no precise formulation of what ‘enough to live on properly’ means, any argument must be inadequate that concludes by making a sharp distinction between those who have enough in this sense and those who don’t. The logic of the argument may be impeccable and the premises may appear to be true. But if you use vague concepts in precise arguments you may well end up with distortions.

      Using the tool

      There are many more ways of legitimately objecting to an argument without actually refuting it. The important thing is to keep in mind the difference between refutation and other forms of objection and to be clear about what form of objection you’re offering.

      SEE ALSO

      1 1.4 Validity and soundness

      2 1.5 Invalidity

      3 3.4 Bivalence and the excluded middle

      READING

       Imre Lakatos (1976/2015). Proofs and Refutations

       Karl Popper (1963). Conjectures and Refutations

       * Jamie Whyte (2005). Crimes Against Logic

       * Julian Baggini (2008). The Duck That Won the Lottery and 99 Other Bad Arguments

       * T. Schick, Jr, and L. Vaughn (2020). How to Think about Weird Things, 8th edn

      Obtaining a guaranteed true conclusion in a deductive argument requires that the argument be sound – that is, it requires both (1) that the argument be valid and (2) that the premises be true (1.4). Unfortunately, the procedure for deciding whether or not a premise is true is much less determinate than the procedure for assessing an argument’s validity. Unless premises are to be justified by arguments whose own premises are to be justified by still other arguments ad infinitum, and unless premises are to circle back on themselves in a loop of justification, there must be a stopping point where fundamental or basic premises are just accepted as true (see Agrippa’s trilemma in 1.1).

      Defining axioms

      For this reason, the concept of an axiom becomes a useful philosophical tool. An axiom is a proposition that acts as a special kind of premise in a specific kind of rational system. Axiomatic systems were first formalised by the Alexandrian geometer Euclid (fl. 300 BCE) in his famous work the Elements. In these kinds of systems, axioms function as initial, anchoring claims that stand in no need of justification – at least from within the system. They are the bedrock of the theoretical system, the basis from which, through various steps of deductive reasoning, the rest of the system is derived. In ideal circumstances, an axiom should be such that no rational agent could possibly object to its use.

      Axiomatic vs natural systems of deduction

      First type of axiom

      As we have defined them, axioms would seem to be pretty powerful premises. Once, however, you consider the types of axiom that there are, their power seems to be somewhat diminished. One type of axiom comprises premises that are true by definition. Perhaps because so few great philosophers have been married, the example of ‘all bachelors are unmarried men’ is usually offered as the paradigmatic example of definitional truths. The problem is that no argument is going to be able to run very far with such an axiom. Axioms of this sort are purely tautological, that is to say, ‘unmarried men’ merely restates in different words the meaning that is already contained in ‘bachelor’. (This sort of proposition is sometimes called – following Immanuel Kant – an ‘analytic’ proposition. See 4.3.) They are therefore spectacularly uninformative sentences (except to someone who doesn’t know what ‘bachelor’ means). So, they are unlikely to help yield informative conclusions in an argument.

      Second type of axiom

      Another type of axiom is also true by definition, but in a slightly more interesting way. Many regions of mathematics and geometry rest on their axioms, and it’s only by accepting these basic axioms that more complex proofs can be constructed within those regions. You might call these propositions ‘primitive’ sentences within the system (7.7). For example, it is an axiom of Euclidean geometry that the shortest distance between any two points is a straight line. But while axioms like these are vital in geometry and mathematics, they merely stipulate what is true within the particular system of geometry or mathematics to which they belong. Their truth is guaranteed, but only in a limited way – that is, only within the context in which they’re defined. Used in this way, axioms’ acceptability rises or falls with the acceptability of the theoretical system as a whole.

      Axioms for all?

      So, some axioms aren’t terribly informative, while others are limited to specific contexts. Some may find this account rather unsatisfactory and object to it. Aren’t there any ‘universal axioms’ that are both secure and informative in all contexts universally, for all thinkers, no matter what? Some philosophers

Скачать книгу