The Philosopher's Toolkit. Julian Baggini

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу The Philosopher's Toolkit - Julian Baggini страница 23

The Philosopher's Toolkit - Julian  Baggini

Скачать книгу

the answer that’s most commonly advanced: probability.

      Objective and subjective probability

      We can distinguish between objective and subjective probability. Objective probability is where what will happen is genuinely indeterminate. Radioactive decay could be one example. For any given atom of a radioactive material, the probability of it decaying over the period of its half‐life is 50–50. This means that, if you were to take ten such atoms, it is likely that five will decay over the period of the element’s half‐life, while five will not decay. On at least some interpretations in physics, it’s genuinely indeterminate which atoms will fall into which category.

      Subjective probability, on the other hand, refers to cases where there may be no actual indeterminacy, but some particular mind or set of minds makes a probability judgement about the likelihood of some event. These subjects do so because they lack complete information about the causes that will determine the event. Their ignorance requires them to make a probabilistic assessment, usually by assigning a probability based on the number of occurrences of each outcome over a long sequence in the past.

      So, for example, if we toss a coin, cover it, and ask you to bet on heads or tails, the outcome has already been determined. Since you don’t know what it is, you have to use your knowledge that heads and tails over the long run fall 50–50 to assign a 50 per cent probability that it’s a head and a 50 per cent probability that it’s a tail. If you could see the coin, there would be no 50–50 about it. You’d know the side that’s up with, in fact, 100 per cent certainty.

      The odds set by gamblers and handicappers at horse races are also species of subjective probability. The posted odds record simply what the many people betting on the race subjectively believe about the outcome, not the real chance of any horse’s crossing the finish line first.

      Certainty and validity

      If you have a valid deductive argument, then its conclusion is often said to follow from the premises with certainty. Many inquirers, however, demand not only that conclusions follow with certainty but that the conclusions themselves be certainly true. Consider the difference between the following arguments:

      1 If it rained last night, England will probably win the match.

      2 It rained last night.

      3 Therefore, England will probably win the match.

      1 It’s certainly true that no parallel lines intersect.

      2 These two lines are parallel.

      3 Therefore, these two lines certainly do not intersect.

      The conclusion of the first argument clearly enters only a probable claim. The conclusion of the second argument, in contrast to the first, enters a certain claim. But here’s the rub: both examples present valid deductive arguments. Both arguments possess valid forms. Therefore, in both arguments the conclusion follows with certainty – i.e. the truth of the premises guarantees the truth of the conclusion – even though the content of one conclusion enters merely a probable claim, while that of the other enters a claim of certainty.

      You must therefore distinguish between (1) whether or not the conclusion of an argument follows from the premises with certainty or some probability, and (2) whether or not the conclusion of an argument advances a statement the content of which concerns matters of probability or certainty.

      Philosophical theories

      But what about philosophical theories? It would seem that if certainty in philosophical theories were attainable, there would be little or no dispute among competent philosophers about which are true and which false – but, in fact, there seems to be a lot of dispute. Does this mean that the truth of philosophical theories is essentially indeterminate? Is deep disagreement a fundamental characteristic of philosophical inquiry?

      Others of a more sceptical bent are, if you’ll pardon the pun, not so certain about the extent to which anything has been proven, at least with certainty, in philosophy. Accepting a lack of certainty can from their point of view be seen as a matter of philosophical maturity.

      SEE ALSO

      1 1.2 Deduction

      2 1.4 Validity and soundness

      3 1.5 Invalidity

      4 1.9 Axioms

      5 1.12 Tautologies, self‐contradictions, and the law of non‐contradiction

      READING

       Ludwig Wittgenstein (1969). On Certainty, §115, §341

       * Barbara J. Shapiro (1983). Probability and Certainty in Seventeenth‐Century England

       Peter Klein (1992). Certainty. In: A Companion to Epistemology (eds J. Dancy and E. Sosa), 61–64

       * D.H. Mellor (2005). Probability: A Philosophical Introduction

       * Alan Hájek (2019). Interpretations of probability. In: The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ed. Edward N. Zalta), Fall 2019 edn

      Tautology and self‐contradiction fall at opposite ends of a spectrum: the former is a sentence that’s necessarily true, and the latter a sentence that’s necessarily false. Despite being in this sense poles apart, they’re actually intimately related.

      In logic, however, ‘tautology’ has a more precisely defined meaning. A tautology is a statement that, because of its logical structure, is true in every circumstance – or, as some say, in every possible world. Tautologies are in this sense logical truths or necessary truths. Take, for example:

      p or not‐p.

Скачать книгу