This Is Bioethics. Udo Schüklenk

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу This Is Bioethics - Udo Schüklenk страница 8

This Is Bioethics - Udo Schüklenk

Скачать книгу

do. Of course, many people today are atheists2 or agnostics3, and many of those who are not atheists hold a large number of different deities dear to their hearts, all with competing action guidance derived from their respective sources of godly wisdom. For all we know, the taxi driver and engineer might just reply that that is how they feel, or possibly even think, about the problem at hand. Let us leave aside, for a moment, that in ancient Greece there were no taxi drivers or engineers as we understand them today. During those times their approach to ethics would have led to them being labeled as Sophists4, that is a group of philosophers who subscribe to the view that there are no objectively right or wrong answers to ethical questions, and that answers to ethical questions are at best reflective of someone’s subjective, strongly held beliefs or feelings. What gave way to the birth of modern ethics were philosophers like Plato5 and his teacher Socrates who both believed that we can actually give right or wrong answers to questions about what is ethically good or bad. We will return to their take on ethics in a moment. How might the medical doctor in our example respond to the ratings agency’s ethical challenge? Trying to do better than the Sophists of the world, she could refer to guidance documents issued, for instance by her national medical association’s ethics people6, or those issued by the World Medical Association7, a worldwide umbrella organization of national medical associations, or possibly the World Health Organization8. But what if these organizations have actually omitted to address the problem at hand in their guidance documents? And, even if they haven’t, quotes from a document don’t constitute an ethical justification. What if the document quoted got it wrong? It turns out, we have good reason to be skeptical about famous historical medical guidance documents such as the Hippocratic Oath9. Robert M. Veatch explains why the Hippocratic Oath isn’t a document medical professionals ought to aspire to. According to Veatch just about everything is wrong about it, from its pledge to questionable Greek deities to a cultish understanding of medicine as a secretive practice to practical guidance that prioritizes individual patient interest always over the greater good of the society (Veatch 2012a, 10–29). To put it in Veatch’s own words, ‘the Oath is so controversial and so offensive that it can no longer stand alongside religious and secular alternatives. […] The Hippocratic Oath is unacceptable to any thinking person. It should offend the patient and challenge the health care professional to look elsewhere for moral authority’ (Veatch 2012a, 1). Veatch tells us, somewhat reassuringly, that the Oath today is used in so many variations in the world’s medical schools that sometimes only fragments of the original document seem to remain (Veatch 2012b).

      1.7 Theologians will be able to tell us what a respective religion would make of the problem at hand. Legal experts could tell us what the law currently says with regard to any of these issues; they might even bravely venture into an analysis suggesting that the law ought to be changed, if they find it to be a violation of their country’s constitutional values. Health care professionals should be able to enlighten us with regard to what their professional values have to contribute to these difficult questions. Sociologists do what sociologists do best, they will ask other people, say taxi drivers, philosophy students, or a representative sample of a given group of people, what their take is on these questions. None of these discipline‐specific responses is capable of enlightening us in a moral or ethical sense. The problems flagged earlier can all be read as asking fundamental ethical questions, namely: Is it ethical to alter

Скачать книгу