This Is Bioethics. Udo Schüklenk

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу This Is Bioethics - Udo Schüklenk страница 9

This Is Bioethics - Udo Schüklenk

Скачать книгу

clinical research purposes? Is abortion immoral? Is the criminalization of assisted dying ethically defensible? Bioethics relies first and foremost on ethics to sustain reasonable defensible answers to these questions. However, it is not the type of ethics that many armchair philosophers would recognize as traditional philosophical ethics. There can be no doubt that bioethical reasoning is not as deep or watertight as, for instance, meta‐ethical reasoning aims to be. Rather, with few notable exceptions, it aims to use the normative frameworks, that we will be looking at, as a rough guide indicative of where, say a utilitarian analysis would lead us when we consider the morality of abortion and infanticide. These frameworks are also useful as tools of critical analysis. They offer us some pretty good guidance and guidance justification on the types of criteria that we might apply when we go about asking, for instance whether abortion is a morally good or bad thing. They could even help us taking a considered ethical stance on markers of fetal development that are frequently argued over by activists and legislators alike. Say, does the moment of conception confer moral standing on the developing human? Or, does the capacity to feel anything matter? Does it matter whether an embryo would be capable of surviving outside the pregnant woman’s womb? These are the types of questions that ethical theories can indeed shed new light on.

      1.9 In the 1850s, the American Medical Association (AMA) was busy developing the content of its Code of Medical Ethics. At the time James L. Phelps, an influential Christian doctor in New York, tried to insert in this code a professional obligation for doctors to preach the truth of the Christian gospel. He referred to ‘the paramount duty of the profession to their patients not only as regards their body in disease, but also the higher interests of the immortal soul. And hence, also the just claim of religion, the great anaesthetics of the immortal mind, to be considered an element of medicine or the healing art’ (Baker, 2013, 181).

      1.10 His fellow doctors at the AMA rejected his approach. They aimed instead for a secular code of medical ethics, and also a secular interpretation of professionalism for its members. Their reasons were entirely pragmatic, as you will notice when you read their rationale: ‘the principles promulgated by this code have been assumed as a common ground upon which every member of the Association may stand, without reference to the distinctive principles or doctrines which distinguish the various religious societies existing among the vastly extended and diversified population of our country’ (Baker, 2013, 181).

      1.11 There are a number of problems with religious approaches to ethics. An obvious one is that many competing religions and claims about God or gods exist. It is in the nature of these claims that they cannot be tested. They rely entirely on belief. Given that we cannot know which of these gods – if any – is the right one, we are better off, in assuming with Plato that even if a God or gods exist, they would also need sound ethical reasons for their ethical judgments. Many people doubt the very idea that a God exists, mostly because of the enduring nature of the terrible evil that persists in the world. This just does not seem to gel well with the idea of an all‐knowing, all‐powerful and good God of most monotheistic religions. In any case, we do not have to settle the difficult question of whether a God or gods exist, thanks to an ancient Greek philosopher, Plato.

      1.13 Euthyphro’s relatives thoroughly disagree with his actions. When Socrates (i.e. Plato’s protagonist) questions Euthyphro, he replies, criticizing his relatives, ‘Which shows, Socrates, how little they know what the gods think about piety and impiety.’ The dialogue goes on for some time, and during the course of it Socrates makes among others a crucial point that is salient to the question of the relationship between religion and ethics: He asks whether something is good because the God or the gods approve of it, or does God (or do the gods) approve of it because it is good. This is a crucial question, because if something is good only because God or the gods approve of it, ultimately what is good would depend entirely on God’s or the gods’ preferences. For all we know God (or the gods) could have approved of Euthyphro’s actions. Slavery might be ok, too. This take implies that the act in question is neither intrinsically good nor bad, because it is entirely dependent on what God’s or the gods’ take is on the issue at hand. It is doubtful that you consider this answer persuasive. Surely, if God or gods exist, they need to have some sort of ethical reason for saying that something is morally wrong. Their answer cannot be completely arbitrary.

      1.14 This leads us to an alternative answer to the question. That answer suggests that some actions are good or bad as such, and that we are able to evaluate such acts by means of using the tools of ethical analysis. Or, as Gordon Graham suggests, ‘Plato’s arguments in Euthyphro seems [sic!] to show that … religion cannot logically serve as a ground for morality’ (Graham 2004, 185–188).

      Public bioethical discourse (or public policy discourse) is actually a meeting ground of the diverse moral traditions that make up our society. Some of these moral traditions have religious inspiration, but that does not necessarily disqualify them as

Скачать книгу