Value. Frederick Harry Pitts

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Value - Frederick Harry Pitts страница 6

Value - Frederick Harry Pitts

Скачать книгу

Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as Nature’s Economics. Cambridge University Press, p. 265.

      4  4 M. Mazzucato, 2019. The Value of Everything: Making and Taking in the Global Economy. London: Penguin, p. 7.

      5  5 Mazzucato 2019, p. 8.

      6  6 Mazzucato 2019, pp. 7, 22.

      7  7 R. L. Heilbroner, 1983. The Problem of Value in the Constitution of Economic Thought. Social Research, 50(2), pp. 253–77 (pp. 253–6).

      8  8 Aristotle, 2000. The Politics. Trans. T. A. Sinclair. London: Penguin; Aristotle, 2004. Nicomachean Ethics. Trans. J. A. K. Thompson. London: Penguin; Mirowski 1989, p. 145; A. Monroe, ed., 1924. Early Economic Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, p. 27.

      9  9 A. Dinerstein and M. Neary, 2002. From Here to Utopia: Finding Inspiration for the Labour Debate. In A. Dinerstein and M. Neary (eds.), The Labour Debate: An Investigation into the Theory and Reality of Capitalist Work. Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 1–26 (p. 13).

      10 10 Heilbroner 1983, pp. 253–6; Mirowski 1989.

      Substantialist approaches to value posit the labour content of a good or service as ‘an order-bestowing force’, as opposed to anything external to it.1 Substantialist theories of value see value as carried and conserved within things, either inhering within the things themselves or inserted there by the labour that created them. They rest on a series of defining positions: the ascription of a natural basis to economic value; the suggestion that value is conserved from the production through to the exchange of products; the ‘reification’ of the economy as an orderly ‘law-governed structure’ akin to nature; the proposal of an ‘invariant standard’ of value; the policing of a boundary between activities productive and unproductive of value; the conviction that the sphere of production is where value is determined; and the resulting ‘relegation’ of money to a purely ‘epiphenomenal status’ expressive of embodied labour.2 As with so much else in value theory, we can trace this line of interpretation to Aristotle, who located in labour a common element underlying the mystery of the equivalent exchange of diverse goods.3

      From mercantilism onwards, the trajectory of substantialism and associated ‘objective’ theories of value from the seventeenth century was also deeply imbricated in social and political shifts, and served the purposes of different actors at different times in different places, with consequences by turns reformist, reactionary and revolutionary. Mercantilism buttressed the social power of the rising merchant class with a zero-sum understanding of value as bound within national borders in the face of expanding international trade; physiocracy buttressed the power of agriculturalists against mercantile interests; classical political economy, the power of industrialists against feudal remnants; and Marx’s version of the labour theory of value, the power of the increasingly assertive proletariat against the industrialists. Today, the national populist tenor of the times grants conservationist appreciations of value as a zero-sum game or substance in time and space fresh political potency, rendering the study of substance theories of value newly relevant. The present-day salience of such thinking shows that the problem of value is by no means a drily academic topic, but one that touches everyday life and current affairs.

      The mercantilist understanding of the economy – which reappears today in the return of protectionist nationalisms – suggested that a system of equivalent exchange must always mean, in the words of Francis Bacon, that ‘whatever is somewhere gotten is somewhere lost’, justifying inter-country rivalry on the basis that ‘trade is a zero-sum game’.9 Value is here taken to be something conserved, and, to the extent that the exchange in which it features is conducted with the national currency, containable within the borders of the state from which it arose. Hence, the positive trade balance – back on the lips of the post-liberal right today – comes to represent the conservation and augmentation of the value substance.

      Another element of classical substantialism that crops up in the intellectual imaginary of contemporary populisms of both right and left is the positioning of sections of the economy that are ‘productive’ of value against those that are ‘unproductive’ of value. Such a distinction is intrinsic to theories of value that rest on a ‘conservation principle’. No substantialism can successfully free itself of the presumption of the unproductiveness of one economic activity or another, because ‘the imposition of conservation principles in the context of a substance theory of value essentially dictates the existence of such categories’. The French physiocrats ‘were the first to make the postulation of unproductive sectors a hallmark of their analysis’, and from this it ‘became the hallmark of a substance theory of value’.10

Скачать книгу