A Concise Companion to Visual Culture. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу A Concise Companion to Visual Culture - Группа авторов страница 20

A Concise Companion to Visual Culture - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

the emergence of visual culture.1 I want to review his aptly entitled essay “Other Criteria” (Steinberg 1972a) in detail and to demonstrate how it serves as a key text that contributes to this rupture within art history out of which visual culture emerged. While its final part, which included “The Flatbed Picture Plane” section, was first published in Artforum in March 1972, under the title “Reflections on the State of Criticism” (see Steinberg 1972b), Steinberg notes that “Other Criteria” was incubated as a lecture delivered four years earlier at the Metropolitan Museum of Art in New York in March 1968. (Subsequent citations here will refer to the published essay in Other Criteria and will use the acronym “OC.” followed by page numbers.) While Clement Greenberg and the formalist critics emphasized flatness in color field and other forms of modernist painting, this characteristic had been understood solely in terms of a vertical orientation and viewing experience. Steinberg’s disdain for Greenberg and the flatness argument is captured in marginal handwritten notes in his personal copy of the reprint of Greenberg’s 1960 “Modernist Painting” six years later, in Gregory Battcock’s The New Art: A Critical Anthology—to which Steinberg, too, contributed an essay (a reprint of “Contemporary Art and the Plight of Its Public”). Where Greenberg writes “and so Modernist painting oriented itself to flatness as it did to nothing else” (Battcock 1966, 103), Steinberg mockingly retorts, at the bottom of the page: “No. This it shares with pancakes.” That is because Greenberg’s ideas about flatness and medium specificity never addressed what Steinberg referred to as painting’s relationship with the viewer’s perception, or with its “psychic mode of address” (OC 84). Steinberg believed that a radical change had occurred that the formalists could not register, a change regarding “how the artist’s pictorial surface tilts into the space of the viewer’s imagination” (OC 82). The tilting to which Steinberg alludes here is the pictorial surface’s becoming horizontal independently of whether it was hung on a wall or not. Steinberg elaborates further:

      To repeat: it is not the actual physical placement of the image that counts. There is no law against hanging a rug on a wall, or reproducing a narrative picture as a mosaic floor. What I have in mind is the psychic address of the image, its special mode of imaginative confrontation, and I tend to regard the tilt of the picture plane from vertical to horizontal as expressive of the most radical shift in the subject matter of art, the shift from nature to culture. (OC 84)

      In order to understand this transformation, Steinberg introduced the concept of the flatbed picture plane as a major innovation in mid‐twentieth century avant‐garde art.

      But something happened in painting around 1950—most conspicuously (at least within my experience) in the work of Robert Rauschenberg and Dubuffet. We can still hang their pictures—just as we tack up maps and architectural plans, or nail a horseshoe to the wall for good luck. Yet these pictures no longer simulate vertical fields, but opaque flatbed horizontals. They no more depend on a head‐to‐toe correspondence with human posture than a newspaper does. The flatbed picture plane makes its symbolic allusion to hard surfaces such as tabletops, studio floors, charts, bulletin boards—any receptor surface on which objects are scattered, on which data is entered, on which information may be received, printed, impressed—whether coherently or in confusion. The pictures of the last fifteen to twenty years insist on a radically new orientation, in which the painted surface is no longer the analogue of a visual experience of nature but of operational processes. (OC 84)

      This is a bold and prophetic passage, which refuses to read Rauschenberg’s work in the traditional terms of pictorial aesthetics. Instead, Steinberg argues that one must address the flatbed picture plane and its horizontal demand as a dense field of data or visual information, a field that is transmitted to the viewer by way of its “receptor surface” and that requires the viewer’s active perceptual and conceptual engagement. Through the deployment of language that resonates with our own contemporary digital era of computational media and “operational processes,” Steinberg captures how the logic of the information age reframes our understanding of Rauschenberg’s combine paintings. Indeed, Steinberg suggests that analogical thinking is no longer relevant to the flatbed picture plane because “the painted surface is no longer the analogue of a visual experience of nature” (OC, 82). This informational approach to Rauschenberg and his combines is also reminiscent of John Berger’s considerations in his contemporaneous Ways of Seeing—in a project strongly indebted to Walter Benjamin—when he talks about the transformation of painting and the emergence of visual culture in the era of its reproduction and transmission. “In the age of pictorial reproduction, the meaning of paintings is no longer attached to them; their meaning becomes transmittable: that is to say it becomes information of a sort, and like all information, it is either put to use or ignored; information carries no special authority within itself” (Berger 1972, 24). Some of Steinberg’s language and figures are quite similar to those we find in Berger’s foundational text and television program for the emergence of visual culture. For example, the figure of the bulletin board as the site for posting a diverse range of visual materials is also embedded in Berger’s democratic argument that bulletin boards are the new museums of visual culture. Berger writes:

      With this paradigm shift, art objects

Скачать книгу