This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter страница 13

This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter

Скачать книгу

this second book. (They say that, as scientists, they are “in the business of describing, not evaluating”.) When they scan your brain, the helmet is simply unable to detect things anything that philosophers call normative – like good and bad, right and wrong, justified and unjustified.3 It simply includes in the book whatever beliefs you in fact do have, for better or worse. If you want to know which beliefs from Your Book of Beliefs belong in Your Book of Justified Beliefs (where being “justified” is a normative matter), you need to do some epistemology, which is the area of philosophy that studies this kind of thing. Epistemology, if done well, can help you figure out not only which (if any) beliefs you have are epistemically justified, but also which ones are known, and even how much knowledge you have.

      1.8 Fortunately, you already have a decent grip – before doing much or any epistemology – of which beliefs of yours seem already like the best candidates for justified beliefs (and which ones don't). Looking through Your Book of Beliefs, you notice the first two entries as:

      B1 (Belief 1). Rental prices will continue to increase in London in the coming year.

      B2. There are ghosts.

      Principle of Sufficient Difference: if there is some normative difference between X and Y, there must be some further non‐normative difference between X and Y that is responsible for this normative difference: that is, there must be some non‐normative feature F such that (i) X has F, (ii) Y lacks F, and (iii) this difference is responsible for the normative difference between X and Y.

      Note that the Principle of Sufficient Difference is not itself a full‐blown method for determining which of your beliefs are justified. But it is a principle that any good method you apply with that aim in mind will have to respect. (Consider that a method that did not respect this principle would have to allow, for example, that two beliefs could have all the same properties with the exception that one of them is justified and the other is not. But that would be quite a pill to swallow.)

      1.12 But what might such a feature be? What seems to favorably distinguish your belief that rental prices will continue to increase in London in the coming year from your belief that there are ghosts? As you look through the pages of Your Book of Beliefs, you notice a good candidate for such a feature: you find various other entries that support B1. By ‘support’ here, what is meant is: entries that might serve as premises of good arguments, arguments that support B1. For example, you come across these entries:

       B645. There will not be an increase in the supply of housing in London during the coming year.

       B646. There will be increased demand for housing in London during the coming year.

       B87. Price will increase if there is an increase in demand without an increase in supply.

      B645, B646, and B87 all support B1. You don't see any other beliefs that support the ghost belief. So here's one difference between B1 and B2: B1 is supported by further beliefs, and B1 is not. Perhaps extrapolating from this difference will give us a good rule for determining which beliefs get to be entries in Your Book of Justified Beliefs:

      Supporting Belief Rule: an entry in Your Book of Beliefs gets to be an entry in Your Book of Justified Beliefs iff it is supported by further beliefs.

      The Supporting Belief Rule seems like a promising idea until you notice that there's another entry in the book:

       B465789. Your friends at school saw a ghost when they were camping.

      You still think that B2 isn't justified, but the Supporting Belief Rule suggests that it is justified – after all, it is supported by a further belief: B465789.

      1.13 The Supporting Belief Rule isn't a good rule. If it's silly to believe in ghosts, it's silly to believe that your friends saw a ghost. If a silly belief supports another silly belief, they remain equally silly, and neither seems to be a good candidate for justification. (Compare: you can't boost the strength of a weak link in a chain by supporting it with another weak link.) The trouble with the Supporting Belief Rule, then, seems to be that it doesn't place any sensible restrictions on which beliefs could confer justification by providing this support.

      1.14 To fix this, we might modify the rule as follows:

      That's better, surely, for it explains why B2 doesn't get into Your Book of Justified Beliefs. It isn't justified, because the only beliefs that support it are unjustified. Notice, however, that if we move to the Supporting Justified Belief Rule, we face a new and entirely different problem.

      1.15 In explaining why B1 is justified, you cited further beliefs (i.e. B645, B646, and B87). There's a nice little argument that takes you from these beliefs to B1, but the argument doesn't justify B1 unless its premises are themselves justified. So: are B645, B646, and B87 justified or not?

      1.16 The Supporting Justified Belief Rule tells us that we need more justified beliefs (and not merely more beliefs) that support B645, B646, and B87 if these beliefs are going to justify B1. Convinced that B1 really is justified, you press on. Surely something must support B645, B646, and B87. So surely these further beliefs contained

Скачать книгу