This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter страница 16

This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter

Скачать книгу

to cite R at the appropriate point in the series.

      Faced with an infinite chain of reasons to cite, it is more likely that, at some point along the chain, S has the disposition to offer a guess or become bored with the whole enterprise (instead of having the epistemically credible disposition to continue citing reasons). There is good reason to think, then, that for a great many cases, S does not possess the relevant second‐order dispositions whatsoever.

      1.36 Let's set aside the Argument from Finite Minds and consider an entirely different kind of worry that infinitism faces, one that doesn't concern issues to do with human cognitive limitations. To this end, consider that one of the main motivations for infinitism is a desire to satisfy this principle:

      Principle of Avoiding Arbitrariness: for all propositions, x, if x is warranted for a person, S, at t, then there is some reason, r1, available to S for x at t; and there is some reason, r2, available to S for r1 at t, etc., and there is no last reason in the series.

      (Klein 2005, p. 136)

      Infinitists want to satisfy this principle in the main because they think a belief that isn't supported by such a set of non‐circular reasons will be held on the basis of a foundational belief that is itself arbitrary, since no further belief would support it.

      1.39 While considerations such as these might be good reasons for someone to believe that you're in pain, why would you need them to justifiably form this belief? How could such considerations account for the fact that it would be right for you to be much more confident that you're in pain than you are confident that any of the supporting reasons you've just mentioned are true?

      1.40 This general idea is captured famously by Ludwig Wittgenstein in his posthumous On Certainty (1969) in the following passages, where Wittgenstein suggests it would not be promising to adduce what is less certain to one in the service of supporting what is more certain to one.

      My having two hands is, in normal circumstances, as certain as anything that I could produce in evidence for it. That is why I am not in a position to take the sight of my hand as evidence for it.

      (OC, §250)

      If a blind man were to ask me “Have you got two hands?” I should not make sure by looking. If I were to have any doubt of it, then I don't know why I should trust my eyes. For why shouldn't I test my eyes by looking to find out whether I see my two hands? What is to be tested by what?

      (OC, §125)

      1.42 Think about your two books, Your Book of Beliefs and Your Book of Justified Beliefs. The Supporting Justified Belief Rule tells us that a belief in the first book, B1, earns a place in the second iff it's supported by other beliefs that have a place in the second book. If we adhere to this rule and there's a finite (but non‐zero) number of entries in Your Book of Justified Beliefs, infinitism must be mistaken. Let's now consider an alternative to infinitism, coherentism.

      1.43 Imagine that you have Your Book of Beliefs in hand. A team of epistemologists has promised to send you a copy of Your Book of Justified Beliefs once they finish a thorough investigation of you, your beliefs, and your belief‐forming habits. Curiosity gets the better of you, so you start to wonder which entries in your book will be entries in theirs. The Supporting Justified Belief Rule tells you this much: if any of your beliefs is included in both books, it's because there's something in both books that supports it. You start to look for connections between the entries. You discover that you can group the entries into categories like this:

       Entries that fit with a significant

Скачать книгу