This Is Epistemology. J. Adam Carter
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу This Is Epistemology - J. Adam Carter страница 30
2.7 The Return of Direct Realism
2.49 As the popularity of indirect realism waned, naïve realism came back into fashion. One nice thing about direct realism is that it allows for the possibility that we're in direct contact with things in the external world. Thus, when we're not hallucinating, it might seem that experience gives us strong support for our beliefs about the external world – when such things are made manifest, we needn't worry that our evidence isn't strong enough to justify belief.
2.50 The challenge for the direct realist is to account for the possibility of hallucination and illusion. This is no trivial task. We can only gesture at some ideas about how the direct realist might address the concerns discussed above.
2.51 Let's start with illusion. In cases of illusion, the things we see appear to have properties that they don't actually have. Think about the bent stick. To the hand, it is straight. To the eye, it is bent or broken. How can we reconcile the fact that the thing we're immediately aware of is both bent and straight (or unbroken and broken)? We can't. Nothing can be both of those ways at once. However, think about Halloween. Suppose you've been invited to a Halloween party and you want to look like a vampire. What do you do? You can't become a vampire. You could at best make yourself look like a vampire, but we'll assume that it's not possible to become a creature of the night. What you do is remain a non‐vampire and then put on a costume, make‐up, etc. to create the appearance of being a vampire. Or a judge. Or a nurse. Or a cat. Or a whatever. There is no problem with some single object having at once these two properties: being a human (who isn't a vampire) and being something that looks like a vampire.
2.52 Although nothing can be both F and non‐F at the same time, something can be F and an apparent non‐F at the same time. To account for the possibility of illusion, the direct realist might say that when we are dealing with a case of perceptual illusion, we are directly aware of an OMO and its properties. These include properties like having a certain shape and color and having a certain apparent shape and apparent color. A wall can be both white (its color) and appear yellow (its apparent color). A coin can be both circular (its shape) and appear elliptical (its apparent shape). You can be both a non‐vampiric human (your kind) and appear to be a vampire (your apparent kind). As long as an object's apparent properties are understood as properties that this object has (given its non‐appearance properties, the conditions under which it is perceived), illusion might be no problem for the direct realist.
2.53 It would seem that this strategy isn't useful for dealing with hallucination. In hallucination, there is supposed to be nothing that can be the object of awareness. With no object, no appeals to the distinction between kinds of properties that an object can have will work. The direct realist might pursue a divide‐and‐conquer strategy and appeal to the disjunctive theory of experience to fend off the Argument from Hallucination. The argument starts from the idea that it can appear just the way things do now; you perceive a book before you even know if you're hallucinating. It then is supposed to convince us that this means that even when we perceive a book, the IOA isn't a book but must be something that's present in the case of hallucination. The disjunctivist thinks that it's a mistake to model our account of perceptual awareness on the case of hallucination. In the case of perception, we see a book. In the case of hallucination, it's as if we do. Sometimes our experience is a matter of something being made manifest and sometimes it is a matter of it being just as if it is. In one case, experience is a relation between you and an ordinary object. In the other, it's as if it is.
2.54 What makes the disjunctivist view disjunctivist is that it offers a disjunctive account of experience:
Disjunctivism about experience: when an individual has an experience as of something being F, it is either a matter of perceiving an F or a matter of seeming to.14
On this approach, we don't think of experience as the core that a perception and some indistinguishable hallucination have in common. True, a subject might not be able to tell one from the other, but the same might hold true for a lemon and a piece of soap. We wouldn't conclude from this that some lemon and some piece of soap share something in common because some subject couldn't tell the one from the other.
2.55 Because disjunctivist denies that the conscious experience a subject has in the case of perception is identical to the experience in a case of hallucination, they're under no pressure to endorse the Phenomenal Principle. Without it, they can block the Argument from Hallucination. Having denied the principle, they are freed from the idea that the thing we're most immediately aware of must always be as it appears. One of the supposed benefits of this approach is that it opens up the possibility that the evidence or rational support that successful perceptual contact provides is better than that provided by hallucination. As we saw above, some are concerned that if the support provided by experience is not better than the support provided by hallucination, that support on its own isn't enough to justify beliefs about things in the external world. To justify believing, say, that we are holding a tomato, we need something that justifies our rejecting the hypothesis that there is no tomato there and that we're just hallucinating. How could experience furnish this justification if, at bottom, the experience is the very same thing in the case of perception and in hallucination? To justify rejecting the hypothesis that the apparent tomato is just a hallucination, it seems we need a better reason to believe that it is real than to believe that it is merely apparent. But this seems to require that we would have different evidence if it were real than we would if it were apparent. Disjunctivism seems to give us this, but the alternative views do not.
2.56 Philosophers have raised a number of objections to the disjunctivist view, but we want to flag one particular objection that's important in an epistemological setting. The disjunctivist thinks that the experience we have when we perceive a tomato, say, is a relation between the perceiver and a tomato in which the tomato is something that the subject is directly aware of. They will grant that this isn't so when the subject has a hallucination, but insist that we shouldn't think of the conscious episode we have in hallucination as an “ingredient,” or part of what transpires in cases of perception. Let's suppose for a moment that this is