Bioethics. Группа авторов

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Bioethics - Группа авторов страница 60

Bioethics - Группа авторов

Скачать книгу

rephrase this question so that it no longer asks about possible people. We can ask: can it be in, or be against, an actual person’s interests to have been conceived? I shall return to this.

      Suppose, next, that we decide not to have children. Then these possible people never get conceived. Can this affect their interests? Can it, for instance, harm these children?

      The normal answer would be “No.” Professor Hare takes a different view. We can simplify the example he discussed. We suppose that a child is born with some serious disability or abnormality, which is incurable, and would probably make the child’s life, though still worth living, less so than a normal life. We next suppose that unless we perform some operation the child will die; and that, if it does, the parents will have another normal child, whom they wouldn’t have if this child lives. The question is, should we operate?

      The implications of Hare’s view can be better seen in another case. Take a couple who – we assume – live in an age before the world was over‐populated, and who are wondering whether to have children. Suppose next that, if they do, their children’s lives would probably be well worth living. Then, on Hare’s view, if the couple choose not to have these children they would be doing them serious harm. Since there is no over‐population, it would seem to follow that their choice is morally wrong. Most of us, I think, would deny this. We believe that there can be nothing wrong in deciding to remain childless. And if we also ask what Hare would count as over‐population, his conclusion would again be widely disputed. This is another subject to which I shall return.

      The principle with which Hare works is that we should do what is in the best interests of those concerned. Most of us accept some principle of this kind. We may believe that other principles are often more important; but we accept, as one of our principles, something to do with interests, with preferences, or with happiness and misery. As this list suggests, such a principle can take different forms. We need only look at a single difference. The principle can take what I call an “impersonal” form: for example, it can run

      1 We should do what most reduces misery and increases happiness.

      It can instead take a “person‐affecting” form: for example

      1 We should do what harms people the least and benefits them most.

      When we can only affect actual people, those who do or will exist, the difference between these forms of the principle makes, in practice, no difference. But when we can affect who exists, it can make a great difference.

      Return, for instance, to the childless couple in the uncrowded world. According to principle (1) – the “impersonal” principle – they should do what most increases happiness. One of the most effective ways of increasing the quality of happiness is to increase the number of happy people. So the couple ought to have children; their failure to do so is, according to (1), morally wrong.

      Most of us would say: “This just shows the absurdity of the impersonal principle. What we ought to do is make people happy, not make happy people. The right principle is (2), the ‘person‐affecting’ principle. If the couple don’t have children, there is no‐one whom they’ve harmed, or failed to benefit. That is why they have done nothing wrong.”

      This reply involves the rejection of Hare’s view. It assumes that we cannot harm people by preventing their conception. If we can, the childless couple would be doing wrong even on the person‐affecting principle.

      Some of these conclusions are, as I said, striking. I shall now begin to argue towards them. We can avoid these conclusions only if we both accept what I shall call “the restriction of our principles to acts which affect people” and claim that our acts cannot affect possible people. Hare denies the latter; I shall be denying the former. The person‐affecting restriction seems to me, at least in any natural form, unacceptable.

      We can start with one of the two questions that I postponed. Can it be in our interests to have been conceived? Can we benefit from receiving life?

      If we can, the childless couple are again at fault, even on person‐affecting grounds – for if they have children they will be benefitting people, as principle (2) tells them to do.

      We might say: “But we can only benefit if we are made better off than we would otherwise have been. This couple’s children wouldn’t otherwise have been – so they cannot benefit from receiving life.” I have doubts about this reasoning. For one thing, it implies that we cannot benefit people if we save their lives, for here too they wouldn’t otherwise have been. True, there are problems in comparing life with non‐existence. But if we assume that a person’s life has been well worth living, should we not agree that to have saved this person’s life many years ago would be to have done this person a great benefit? And if it can be in a person’s interests to have had his life prolonged, even, say, just after it started, why can it not be in his interests to have had it started?

Скачать книгу