Property. Robert Lamb A.

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Property - Robert Lamb A. страница 6

Property - Robert Lamb A.

Скачать книгу

property specifically, rather than other forms. For example, the right to bequeath an owned holding to another person after death is very often included as a core part of the concept. Yet the ascription of this capacity as a definitive feature of property rights would seem to foreclose, or at the least limit, certain normative questions about the legitimacy of the state acting to tax or redistribute things that are owned. If having the right to bequeath my property is part of what it means to own something, then the case for taxing the transfer becomes a much harder sell. On the other hand, any decision to deny that the concept of property includes the power to bequeath – and instead assume that individuals do not have such rights to hold against the redistributive authority of the state – appears just as guilty of smuggling an equivalent normative claim into an austerely analytic definition. If the right to bequeath property is not part of what it means to own it, there seems no obvious argument against its taxation or even confiscation following the owner’s death.3 Questions about the meaning of private property thus inescapably intrude on questions about its fair distribution. In doing so, they invite consideration of other political concepts, such as freedom, justice, and equality, which will make various appearances during our subsequent discussions.

      An historical approach to property also, in my view, allows us to bypass a contemporary philosophical dispute concerning the nature of property as a concept. This dispute turns on whether the concept of property has any essential characteristics. Some theorists argue that there is a stable and definite conceptual core to the idea of property. James Penner, for instance, suggests that the idea of exclusive use provides the ‘formal essence of the right’ to own property. According to this understanding, ‘the right to property is a right to exclude others from things which is grounded by the interest we have in the use of things’ (Penner 1997: 71, emphasis suppressed). As Penner points out, the concepts of exclusion and use often come together through ownership rights: we are accustomed to thinking of private property as implying our legitimate need or desire to use a particular thing and, correspondingly, requiring that we are able to exclude others from doing so. This combination of exclusion and use does not mean that our ownership rights obtain only in our particular occasions of use – our furniture does not cease belonging to us when we are not immediately using it. The idea of exclusive use signals instead the connection between our rightfully owned property and our purposiveness and intentionality. It captures the fact that property is valuable to us because of the role it plays in our lives, as part of our long-term personal projects. On this construal, property confers a series of benefits on its owner through the exercise of certain liberties. She can, without interference, share, transfer, or derive benefit from, the property in question, as well as enter into various forms of contract concerning it.

      The most influential way of thinking about property in contemporary legal philosophy instead abandons altogether the view of it as a singular concept, and understands it instead to be a ‘bundle’ of discrete and separable legal relations. There have been different ways of conceiving exactly what such a bundle entails, but the basic idea is that we can endeavour to separate the various sticks that comprise it and, in so doing, acquire a better understanding of the nature of the legal and social phenomena at issue. Proponents of the bundle approach claim that it clears away what they regard as a fog of conflation that blinds political and legal discussion of the subject. To appreciate the thinking behind the bundle theory, we need to step back a bit and go over some of the key features of rights themselves. Beyond their expressive, political purposes – which might include the recognition of our dignity or moral standing in a community – rights serve to enable and prohibit our freedoms, making some actions permissible and others impermissible. In the context of property, this function seems straightforward and relates back to our interest in having systematic and permanent protection for specific resources, which become our holdings rather than those of anyone else.

      Not all of the conventional legal relations traditionally associated with the concept of property ownership are, strictly speaking, rights. Philosophers generally follow Wesley Hohfeld’s (1919) understanding of rights as claims, which are characterised by their correlative concept, duties. Rights of this sort imply duties held by others. If the right I have

Скачать книгу