Property. Robert Lamb A.

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Property - Robert Lamb A. страница 7

Property - Robert Lamb A.

Скачать книгу

then it implies a correlative duty in others to respect – and forbear from interference with – my ownership of it. Put crudely, my property right means that, under most circumstances, you are obliged to keep your hands off my stuff and that the relevant legal authority, if required, can enforce this obligation. Not all rights are claims in this sense. It would be unusual to interpret the right to free speech, for example, as a claim that generates a corresponding duty for others. Such a right does not conventionally imply any corresponding obligation that prevents any person from interfering with its exercise, perhaps by talking over you, or otherwise distracting your audience as you address them. Rights to both engage in and disrupt free speech would seem to co-exist coherently, without duties of non-interference appearing on the scene. It arguably makes more sense to construe free speech as what Hohfeld terms a privilege (or liberty) right, which correlates not to obligations but merely to the privileges held by others. When a person has a privilege to undertake an action, what this means is that they are under no duty to refrain from it: privileges are essentially (negative) freedoms to undertake actions without fear of penalty, but they do not entail protective duties imposed on others to enable those actions.

      In an influential essay on the meaning of property, A. M. Honoré lists eleven ‘standard ingredients of ownership’, and thus identifies some of the conceptual sticks that we might expect to find in our bundle of rights. According to him:

      Ownership comprises the right to possess, the right to use, the right to manage, the right to the income of the thing, the right to the capital, the right to security, the rights or incidents of transmissibility and absence of term, the prohibition of harmful use, liability to execution, and the incident of residuarity. (Honoré 1993: 370)

      An entailment of the bundle thesis – and perhaps one of the motivations driving its advocacy – is that the very notion of property as a singular object of study is a product of mistaken, mystified thought. Reference to an overarching concept of ownership would seem to posit an illusory unity to what is not actually one, but numerous legal relationships. We cannot consider such relationships as constituting any kind of singular entity without incurring important misunderstandings of their natures, justifications, and implications. On the bundle account, it makes no sense to analyse ownership as an institution and we should attend instead to specific practices like the right to use or the power to transfer. The concept of property thus vanishes out of sight, with the notion of an owner a misleading oversimplification, perhaps even a category error, with no possible basis in reality.4 It emerges as a fiction, a weirdly inaccurate kind of shorthand device that encourages the reification of a popular idea that blinds us to a proper understanding of social and legal phenomena.

      In this book, I highlight important parts of the tradition of thinking and arguing about property. I examine and assess conceptions and normative contestations of property advanced by different individuals, who are often in direct conversation with each other. We will consider each of these theories on their own terms, insofar as the discussion will not assume an established definition of property to compare against their individual understandings. Such an author-centred analysis avoids cementing intellectual traditions into rigid ideologies. Although I will regularly invoke political or theoretical traditions – libertarianism, utilitarianism, anarchism, and so on – I use these labels loosely; as I will make clear, Nozick’s theory does not exhaust the libertarian theory of property and Bentham’s does not define the utilitarian alternative. No individual theory of property is reducible to the intellectual tradition of which it is part or the political ideology it is supposed to represent.5

      The structure of the rest of the book is as follows. In the first chapter, I consider why we might think that private property stands in need of a compelling justification. To explain the urgency of this undertaking – beyond the aforementioned habit of political philosophers surveying the world and asking why it is the way it is – I introduce some of

Скачать книгу