Kant. Andrew Ward

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Kant - Andrew Ward страница 6

Kant - Andrew Ward

Скачать книгу

how particular events in the spatio-temporal world behaved. For no amount of experience could prove that every event has a cause. The universal judgment is here taken to be entirely unrestricted, applying to all past, present and future events in nature, actual and possible. Evidently too, no experience could prove that it is necessary that any event has a cause. Experience can only tell us that such-and-such is or is not the case; it can never tells us that it must or must not be so.

      But if experience will not do the trick, how could the causal principle be proved? The only alternative, Hume contended, is to show that it is true in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved. If the meaning of ‘event’ includes in it ‘having a cause’, then, indeed, we can justifiably assert that every event must have a cause. (Just as we can justifiably assert that every bachelor must be unmarried. In this latter case, the mere analysis of the subject term ‘bachelor’ and the predicate term ‘unmarried’ reveals that to deny the judgment would be self-contradictory.) But, as Hume argued, there simply is no such connection of meaning between the subject and the predicate terms in the principle ‘Every event must have a cause.’ To deny it is not self-contradictory. In Kantian terminology, the principle is not analytically true.

      Since the principle is not analytically true, and, as Hume contended, this is the only acceptable way to prove that a judgment holds with strict universality and necessity, he concluded that our belief in the principle is unjustified.

      Why, then, do we believe it? Here, Hume gives a psychological answer. It is the constant occurrence, throughout our past experience, of similar changes of state, under the same circumstances, that has led to our belief that the principle is justified. Far from the belief arising from, or being provable by, our rational faculties, it is merely the product of our enlivened imagination. In particular, the necessity that we ascribe to the principle is merely a ‘subjective necessity’ or feeling of inevitability (arising from our experience of past constant conjunctions), and not an objective necessity (not a requirement, discernible in the objects or in our judgment about the objects, that nature is uniform). Accordingly, so far as reason or understanding is concerned, our experience of nature could have been entirely chaotic. Moreover, there is absolutely no rational ground for supposing that our experience – even granting that it has, in fact, been as regular as clockwork up to now – might not turn random, acausal, at any moment in the future. The supposition that the future course of events will resemble the past cannot even be shown to be probable, let alone necessary.

      But he disagreed with Hume about the status of the general principle that every event, or change of state, in nature must have a cause. Although he thought that Hume was correct to maintain that this principle is not analytically true, he rejected what he took to be Hume’s conclusion from this observation: namely, that the principle cannot be justified.

      How, though, can the causal principle legitimately carry necessity and universality, if not in virtue of the meaning of the terms involved?

      To understand Kant’s answer to this question is to be well on the way to understanding many of the central ideas in the Critique of Pure Reason. He was not exaggerating when he claimed that Hume had struck a spark which, if carefully kindled, would produce a new light on metaphysics. For Kant thought that the status of the causal principle could be generalized to take in not only all the leading judgments in metaphysics, but also all the fundamental judgments in two areas of what he saw as unquestionably genuine repositories of knowledge of objects: namely, pure mathematics and pure natural science (pure natural science forms the non-empirical basis of Newtonian physics). And this thought, in turn, led him to conclude that there must be something wrong with Hume’s scepticism. Since, as he affirmed, there certainly are two areas where we can find examples of judgments which, while not analytically true, hold with necessity and universality, viz. in pure mathematics and pure natural science, what is required is not a wholesale dismissal of all such knowledge claims, but an investigation of how such judgments can be true, in those two areas where they clearly exist.

      Kant’s attempt to refute Hume’s causal scepticism and so, too, his investigating how pure mathematics and pure natural science can exist are both intimately connected with his so-called Copernican revolution in philosophy. They are intimately connected, because he came to the conclusion that the only way to explain how mathematics and natural science can exist is by effecting a major turnabout in the way that we conceive the relationship between ourselves (the knowing mind) and the objects of our sense experience (the objects in space and time). His Copernican revolution equally has major repercussions for metaphysics and for morality. This second stage of his revolution will be touched on after I have said something about the first stage: his investigation of the possibility of mathematics and natural science.

      Unfortunately,

Скачать книгу