Kant. Andrew Ward

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Kant - Andrew Ward страница 9

Kant - Andrew Ward

Скачать книгу

must apply to us as moral agents. It would, in short, be impossible for us even to assume freedom of the will (see the Antithesis and Observation of the Third Antinomy). Equally, we should have to renounce our belief in a necessary Being who has created and sustains the universe; since, without the distinction, it is provably impossible that such a Being could exist (see the Antithesis and Observation of the Fourth Antinomy). Lastly, the belief that the soul is simple – and, therewith, the possibility of believing in the continuation of the soul after the death of the body – must be rejected, unless the world of the senses is distinguished from the world as it is in itself (see the Antithesis and Observation of the Second Antinomy).

      Moreover, if it is impossible even to assume the existence of free will, God and the immortality of the soul, without embracing Kant’s Copernican revolution, then since – as he himself argues – these are necessary presuppositions of morality, it follows that the demands of morality must themselves be delusory.That is why Kant asserts:‘I have therefore found it necessary to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith’ (CPR,B xxx; italics original).

      The First Critique, then, not only seeks to explain how there can be universal and necessary knowledge of objects in mathematics and in natural science, it also seeks to leave a space open for morality.As Kant sees it, neither the theoretical nor the practical side to our lives can be sustained on the traditional picture. On his Copernican picture, on the other hand, we can – in fact do – have both. The positive contribution of the Dialectic is to show how it is possible for the moral life to exist – and therewith to lay the ground for the practical proofs of just those central metaphysical claims (concerning freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the existence of God) that, as he had argued earlier, our theoretical reason is, in reality, powerless to prove or disprove.

      Before embarking on a more detailed look at Kant’s system, we need to do two things. First, we need to understand some of his terminology, especially with regard to his division of judgments into three types. Second, we need to understand more fully the status that he accords to judgments in mathematics and natural science.

      Kant identifies three possible types of judgment:

      1 Analytic a priori judgments;

      2 Synthetic a posteriori judgments;

      3 Synthetic a priori judgments.

      In order to explain this threefold division, he further distinguishes between analytic and synthetic judgments, on the one hand, and a priori and a posteriori judgments, on the other. These further distinctions can be explained as follows.

      An analytic judgment is one in which the meaning of the predicate term is included in the meaning of the subject term. Example: ‘All bachelors are unmarried (men).’ Kant notes that the denial of an analytic judgment is self-contradictory (as in ‘It is not the case that all bachelors are unmarried’).

      A synthetic judgment is one in which the meaning of the predicate term is not contained in the meaning of the subject term. Example: ‘All men are mortal.’ Accordingly, the denial of a synthetic judgment is not self-contradictory. (The judgment ‘It is not the case that all men are mortal’ is doubtless false; but it is not self-contradictory, given the meaning of ‘men’ and ‘mortal’, etc.)

      It is worth noting that Kant does not define an a priori judgment as one that claims to hold with necessity and/or universality. For him, an a priori judgment is defined as one that is thought of as holding independently of experience. But if we can discover a judgment that does claim to hold with necessity and/or universality, then we can be sure that it is a priori. Necessity and universality are infallible means of recognizing an a priori judgment.

      Given his definition of an a priori judgment, we can understand Kant’s claim that besides a priori judgments (or principles) there may also be – indeed, are – a priori concepts. For example, he holds that the concept of cause is an a priori concept. By this he means that it is not derived, or formed, from any experience; it is, rather, a concept that we possess independently of experience. Such concepts may well be applied to what can be experienced, although this is not an essential feature of an a priori concept. What is essential is that an a priori concept is a concept that we possess independently of any experience.

      Just as there can be a priori concepts, so there can be a posteriori ones.As one would expect, these are dependent (at least in part) upon experience. Our concept of copper is a posteriori, since it requires experience in order to be formed.

      We can now examine Kant’s division of judgments into three categories. In particular, we need to ask how each type of judgment can be established.

      (1) Analytic a priori judgments. Since every analytic judgment depends, for Kant, only on the meaning of the terms involved, such a judgment can always be established by determining that the meaning of the predicate

Скачать книгу