Kant. Andrew Ward

Чтение книги онлайн.

Читать онлайн книгу Kant - Andrew Ward страница 11

Kant - Andrew Ward

Скачать книгу

a chain of inferences guided throughout by intuition, he arrives at a fully evident and universally valid solution of the problem. (A 716–17/B 744–5)

      In Kantian terminology, the method may be described as producing a proof on the basis of ‘sensible intuition’. More will be said about intuition in the section on space and time. The point to note here about basing a proof on sensible intuition is that it involves recourse to the construction of figures, in a sensuous field, in accordance with our own a priori concepts. This construction can occur either by means of the imagination alone, in what Kant calls ‘pure intuition’, or by means of drawing a figure in reality, e.g. on paper, in what he calls ‘empirical intuition’. But in either case, the construction must employ the a priori geometrical concepts, discounting any contingent features inherent in the drawn figure. And the demonstration itself – for Kant, a ‘demonstration’ can occur only in mathematics – consists in being able to exhibit (A 716/B 744) or observe (A 717/B 745) that certain relations obtain in intuition as a result of the construction. (A more general discussion, which was added in the second edition, is given at B 14–17.)

      Without reference to intuition, Kant’s claim is that there is no possibility of proving any of the axioms or first principles of geometry. Thus, the a priori concepts of triangle, angle,etc., however deeply they are analysed, will never entail that the denial of the judgment concerning the internal angles of a triangle is self-contradictory. Hence, the judgment cannot be an analytic a priori truth. I need to engage in a demonstration, a showing: I need, that is, to go outside the a priori concepts involved and exhibit in intuition, by means of the constructing of a diagram, that the corresponding judgment holds. That is why the a priori judgment is synthetic, and not analytic. Moreover, since geometrical demonstrations essentially involve proving synthetic yet necessary relationships about extension and figure (inherently spatial concepts), geometry is conceived as describing the structure of space. As Kant sees it, geometry is a body of synthetic a priori judgments that determines the properties of space (B 40).

      Although it is not difficult to see why, given Kant’s claim about the manner of proving geometrical judgments, he should argue for a parallel process for arithmetic, it is not so easy to grasp why he thinks that arithmetic, together with pure mechanics, are possible only by means of our possession of an intuition of time. His argument seems to be that, in the case of arithmetic, the various concepts of number are all realized by successive addition or subtraction (succession being a temporal notion); and in the case of mechanics, its fundamental concepts are all concerned in some way with motion (which itself requires a recognition of how the same thing can be in distinct places, viz. through its existence in these distinct places, one after the other).At any event, in his discussion of the synthetic a priori judgments of arithmetic and pure mechanics, he links these judgments with the necessity of our having a sensible intuition of time.

       Criticism of the thesis that mathematical judgments are synthetic a priori

      Second, let us assume that Euclid’s system is a posteriori. As such, the Euclidean axioms can, in principle, be true judgments about the structure of space. Further, since they are based on experience, they must be synthetic (to deny any of them is not self-contradictory). But although the axioms may be true synthetic judgments, they are not, pace Kant, necessarily true. They will be merely true empirical generalizations about the structure of space. Thus the straight line axiom should here be taken as an empirical claim to the effect that since it has always been found in fact that the shortest distance between any two points in space is a straight line – where ‘straight line’ is given some suitable empirical definition, e.g. ‘the path of a light wave in a vacuum’ – it is held, on inductive grounds, that this is always the case. Consequently, the theorems of the system, since they follow logically, by rules of inference from these axioms, will equally express empirical generalizations about the structure of geometrical figures in space. They cannot, therefore, state anything with necessity or strict universality about the structure of space. On the contrary, all the theorems as well as all the axioms will have (at best) a posteriori validity because the content of the axioms – and so the theorems derived from them – are dependent upon experience. On this way of looking at Euclidean geometry, its theorems as well as its axioms will, if true, express synthetic a posteriori judgments about the structure of space.

Скачать книгу