A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value. Группа авторов
Чтение книги онлайн.
Читать онлайн книгу A Companion to Motion Pictures and Public Value - Группа авторов страница 39
Two Problems with Mediated Appreciation
Whence, then, this hostility toward mediated appreciation of nature? I think we can identify two major concerns that might underlie it.
The quotation from Carlson, presented above, suggests the first. His critique of photographs and landscape paintings is based on the fact that, being so different from natural environments, they are simply unable to present enough of the relevant properties of those environments. A static, two-dimensional representation of a forest cannot present to us qualities such as the scent of pine trees, the forest’s changing appearance as the light wanes, the feel of the wind, and so on, all of which are very much relevant to that environment’s aesthetic value. In short, a photo of an environment, such as a forest, just could not have a significant degree of appreciative aptness, any more than, say, an audio recording of a dance performance could. The problem is not with how well the representation has been done; rather the problem lies in the inherent limitations of the medium itself. Call this the “Poverty of Representation” objection to mediated nature appreciation.
A second worry about mediated appreciation can also be extracted from Carlson’s writing about photography. Expanding on the differences between natural environments and photographs, he notes that the appreciation of photographs tends to involve formal and compositional qualities of the two-dimensional image, qualities such as balance, symmetry, and so on. Consider Ansel Adams’ famous photograph Moon and Half-Dome (1960): the image has been carefully composed so as to include a balance between the bright and dark regions, and a central framing of the Moon between the two peaks (King 1992, 262). For a more recent example, consider Max Waugh’s prize-winning photograph of a bison in Yellowstone National Park, Snow Exposure (Figure 3.1). The animal is perfectly centered and Waugh employed a long exposure time to give the falling snow a rope like quality, echoing nicely the texture of the bison’s fur, producing what is almost a “negative image” of the animal.8
Figure 3.1 Snow Exposure (2018), (photo by Max Waugh courtesy of the photographer).
Such formal, compositional properties make for a striking photograph; however, one could argue that they have little to do with the natural object that is represented in the photograph. The problem here is not our previous problem—that photographic representations are incapable of presenting certain properties of their subject matter. Rather, the problem here is that what is appreciated via the representation is not the subject at all, but something else—namely, the composed photographic image. Call this the “Appreciative Shift” objection to mediated nature appreciation.9
The Appreciative Shift objection is easily extended to landscape painting, where the artistic element of compositional choice is, if anything, even more pronounced. If we look at the typical process whereby an artist starts from a sketch done on site and later produces a landscape painting in the studio, we can see how specific compositional choices shape the final image. And we can further extend the objection by noting that the artistic element of photographs and paintings includes not only compositional, formal qualities, such as balance, symmetry and so on, but also expressive qualities. Some painters—Van Gogh furnishes the paradigm example—aimed above all to lend the landscape a certain “quality of feeling” in their representations of it.10 In such cases, the viewer’s focus shifts from the landscape itself to an emotional or expressive quality that the artist has projected onto it.
Neither of these worries about mediated nature appreciation—the Poverty of Representation objection or the Appreciative Shift objection—is misconceived. Each points to a genuine concern about the feasibility of certain forms of mediated nature appreciation. Furthermore, there have been particular practices of nature appreciation for which these objections are highly relevant. The Picturesque tradition of landscape appreciation, to cite the most notorious example, was practically based on the idea of an appreciative shift, wherein direct perception of the landscape itself was replaced by the appreciation of a “better composed” image, either in landscape paintings or devices such as the Claude mirror.11 Although the Picturesque has faded, its spirit lives on in digital photography practices such as the use of filters that allow easy manipulation of colors and detail to adjust an image’s “emotional tone”. Also, the practice of assessing the “scenic quality” of landscape by quantifying the formal features of photographs has been, and remains, an influential technique in much empirical landscape assessment.12 Much philosophical skittishness about mediated nature appreciation is no doubt a reaction to the highly problematic aspects of these appreciative practices.
There are, then, genuine concerns about mediated appreciation of nature in general, concerns that may account for the ongoing neglect of nature film. It is important to note, however, that these concerns arose not from any direct consideration of film itself, but primarily from discussions of photography and landscape painting. In this sense, the neglect of film has been, I think, something of an unintended effect, and a very unfortunate one at that, because a consideration of film offers us, I shall now argue, our best way of responding to these very concerns.
Poverty of Representation and Film
As mentioned above, our two objections to mediated appreciation are not simply misconceived. They have, however, been exaggerated. With respect to the Poverty of Representation objection, for instance, it may be pointed out that the objection garners much of its force from the idea that nature must be understood as an environment. But while an environment may be the subject of a representation of nature, so too may natural objects; indeed natural objects form the primary subject matter in genres such as wildlife painting and wildlife photography.13 It is by no means clear that representations of objects are so inherently impoverished as to fail miserably in appreciative aptness. Wildlife painting and photography present us with the shape, size, and color of an organism, and can be suggestive of its movement and demeanor. Film representations greatly expand the properties of an animal that can be presented, encompassing sound and movement. The important point is that, when it comes to natural objects, the limitations of representational media vary greatly, so focusing only on particular media provides a distorted picture, one we can correct by considering a broader range of art forms and media, particularly film.
The importance of film becomes more apparent when we consider attempts to represent an environment, as opposed to an object. Here appreciative aptness is harder to achieve, given that environments have distinct properties related to the experience of moving through the environment, being enveloped by it, and so on. But one of the distinctive features of film is surely its capacity to convey precisely these sorts of spatial properties. To be sure, watching a film where the camera moves through, and is surrounded by, a certain environment is not the same as moving through and being surrounded by that environment. Also, how exactly we relate perceptually to the space depicted on screen is a large issue for philosophy of film and perception. Yet, it seems clear that cinematic representations can be appreciatively apt with respect to at least some of the immersive spatial features of the environments they depict.
That said, there are certain features of environments and objects that even film will be unable to capture: the smells an object offers, for instance, or the tactile sensations involved in being located within an environment. Perhaps only some kind of science fiction style virtual reality simulation could capture such features (as imagined, for example, by Danto 2004). But even in these cases, there is surely a role for imagination in filling out some of the features of environments that our representations are unable to capture. I can’t feel the pressure of the water against my skin as I watch underwater